Back to Book Reviews

Back to Cercles

 

James Harrington

An Intellectual Biography

 

Rachel Hammersley

 

Oxford: University Press, 2019

Hardcover. xvii+315 p.  ISBN 978-0198809852. £70

 

Reviewed by Warren Chernaik

King’s College London

 

 

 

James Harrington, the author of The Commonwealth of Oceana (1656), is a very odd, puzzling figure, a subject of controversy in his lifetime and posthumously, and a book investigating his writings in their historical context and in the history of political theory should be highly interesting and useful. Though generally recognised as a key figure among the classical republicans of the Early Modern period, Harrington differed from all his fellow republicans in many ways. Rather than providing a model or template for the development of the ideology of republicanism in his time and afterwards, as such influential scholars as John Pocock have argued, Harrington is at best a ‘minority voice’, arguing an independent, idiosyncratic position.(1) Harrington’s political works were all written during a very short period, in two concentrated bursts: The Commonwealth of Oceana was published in 1656, two years after Oliver Cromwell had been become Lord Protector, and followed by a sudden outpouring of pamphlets in 1659 (Hammersley lists nineteen in her index), in the period of uncertainty after Cromwell’s death. The Commonwealth of Oceana, his major work, is not a political tract, but a utopian romance, an allegorical roman à clef, in which, transparently, Oceana is England, Marpesia is Scotland, Panopea is Ireland, and Olpheus Megaletor, Lord Archon, is Oliver Cromwell. Clothed within this fiction is a detailed constitutional settlement, applicable to England in the 1650s, which is intended to serve as a permanent model for an ‘immortal commonwealth’, fortified against vicissitude. Along with Hobbes’s Leviathan, written five years earlier—and the relationship between Hobbes and Harrington is complex—The Commonwealth of Oceana is one of the most important works of political theory of the 17th century, providing ‘a system of politics’ or ‘Political Principles’ applicable beyond the immediate circumstances that prompted the work.

Though Hammersley at times suggests that Harrington cannot be called a classical republican, or a republican of any sort, it is clear that he considered ‘ancient prudence’, as ‘unanimously followed by the Greeks and Romans’, until ‘the liberty of Rome’ was ‘extinguished’ by Julius Caesar, far superior to ‘those ill features of government’ prevalent in his own day: ‘An art whereby some man, or some few men, subject a city or a nation, and rule it according to his or their private interest …the empire of men and not of laws’ [Commonwealth of Oceana : 8-9].

Like Machiavelli, whom he praises as ‘the only politician of later ages’, the greatest of political theorists, ‘having excelled all others’ [10, 221], Harrington sets forth a series of historical examples, largely drawn from ancient Greece and Rome, as lessons for the present. In opposition to Hobbes and other proponents of one-man rule, he argued that monarchy, as likely to be corrupted into tyranny, was the worst of governments. Harrington differed from other classical republicans of his day in his lack of emphasis on the right of resistance: though the idea of consent is central to his arguments, he never tried to justify the right of the people to overthrow a bad monarch. Like his friend Andrew Marvell, writing at a time when ‘the kingdom old’ had been cast ‘into another mould’, he sought to anatomise the process of revolutionary change and to suggest what, in a time of uncertainty, might follow. Harrington was unusual in his time in his economic determinism: for him, the motivating force in historical change was that ‘Empire follows the Balance of Property’, with the inevitability of a scientific principle. According to his disciple Walter Moyle: ‘The Balance of Dominion changes with the Balance of Property, as the Needle in the Compass shifts its Points just as the great Magnet in the Earth changes its Place’.(2)

Harrington’s principal innovation (other than the idea of a secret ballot) was what he called an ‘agrarian law’, limiting the accumulation of property, in land or money, by any individual, abolishing primogeniture and establishing a figure beyond which accumulation was prohibited. Though ownership of property (propriety: what belongs to any individual within the society) is central to Harrington’s thought, he neither advocates the abolition of private property nor, like Locke, the sacred trinity of ‘life, liberty, and property’, seen as inalienable rights.

Hammersley’s book, the product of twenty years of research, includes a chapter which clearly sets forth Harrington’s innovatory doctrine of the balance of property, the material basis of political power, according to which ‘all government is interest, and the predominant interest gives the matter or foundation of the government’.(3) Starting from Aristotle’s conventional distinction between ‘the government of one man, or of the better sort, or of the whole people, which by their more learned names are called monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy’ [Oceana : 10], Harrington, as Hammersley shows, goes on to argue that in any government power must necessarily rest in which of these groups predominates in the possession of land and material goods. Here and in a chapter on ‘Harrington the Republican’, Hammersley gives a lucid account of the specific constitutional proposals set forth in The Commonwealth of Oceana by which ‘an equal balance’ can be achieved and maintained. Excellent chapters, carefully argued, explore ‘the limits of Harrington’s republicanism’ [81-96] and—a topic rarely considered in accounts of Harrington—the philosophical underpinnings of Harrington’s political writings. Harrington’s writings include many references to Harvey’s discoveries about the circulation of the blood, which, as Hammersley shows, provide an insight into his relationship to the New Science of his day [219-226]. An introductory chapter gives a brief account of the development of Harrington’s reputation, the ‘complex and contested legacy of his political thought’ [23], while chapters on ‘Harrington the man’ emphasise his complex, possibly conflicted position as a republican thinker who deeply mourned the death of Charles I. Harrington served the King in a number of capacities, including Gentleman of the Bedchamber in 1647-8, and, according to his biographer and disciple John Toland, ‘He had the good luck to prove very acceptable to the King, who much convers’d with him about Books and Foren Countreys’ [57]. In keeping with her desire to give ‘a fresh account of Harrington’s life and work’ which goes ‘beyond the republican paradigm’ and does not concentrate excessively either on a single work, The Commonwealth of Oceana, or on his place in the republican tradition [22], Hammersley devotes a great deal of attention to Harrington’s less familiar writings, with particular attention to the pamphlet wars of 1659. I found these chapters, arranged topically, on the exchanges between Harrington and his opponents—controversies on politics, religion, history, and philosophy—especially informative.

Though Hammersley has succeeded admirably in presenting a fresh view of Harrington, bringing out ‘the complex relationship between his life, his political activities, and his writings’ [26], there are certain problems implicit in this book’s approach. There is little attempt to relate either Oceana or the pamphlets of 1659 to the immediate political context which impelled Harrington to write these works. Two brief pages on ‘Oceana’s Historical and Intellectual Context’ fleetingly mention the Instrument of Government, the proposed constitution of the Protectorate, but take no stand on Harrington’s attitude towards Cromwell and the Protectorate. Instead we have a summary of what several 20th-century critics have said about the work, and a paragraph on whether Harrington can be associated ‘with the republican movement of the 1650s’ [70]. The excellent chapter on Harrington and political debate in 1659-60, full of illuminating detail, would be even better if it tried to explore the implications of a passage quoted from parliamentary debates: ‘What doth an interregnum signify but that we are without a government at present’ [231]. Another methodological problem is implicit in Hammersley’s title. An ‘intellectual biography’ presumably will deal with the intellectual influences on an author, analytically investigating the formation of his ideas, what he takes from his predecessors and how he differs from them. Though there are many references to Machiavelli and even more to Hobbes in Hammersley’s book, most of them are embedded in references to what other scholars have said, or mention ways in which, in specific details, Harrington’s position differed from these authors. What a distinguished intellectual historian like Hammersley could have provided in this book is a clear account of the trajectory of Harrington’s ideas, with careful attention paid to such figures as Machiavelli, Hobbes, Francis Bacon, John Selden, Aristotle, Cicero, and Livy.

In one chapter, Hammersley’s attempt to decouple Harrington from the republican tradition, seeing him in a different light, seems to me seriously misleading. She makes the valid point that the term ‘democracy’ in the 17th century generally has negative connotations (as in Dryden’s contemptuous ‘drawn to the dregs of a Democracy’), and that this is not so in Harrington. But this does not mean that Harrington should be considered a democratic rather than a republican theorist, or that he endorses a form of democratic government in his imaginary republic. Hammersley’s account is useful in calling attention to the sheer number of references to the term ‘democracy’ in such Harrington treatises as The Art of Law-giving and The Prerogative of Popular Government as well as Oceana. Harrington and his disciple Henry Neville frequently use the term to apply to a form of government in which ‘the chief part of the Soveraign Power, and the exercise of it, resides in the People, a government in which ‘the people have the election of the Senate’, or ‘a meer popular Council, giving Law unto a King’.  At times Harrington uses ‘Democraticall’ as a synonym for ‘Popular’, contrasting ‘the Few , or the Natural Aristocracy’ with ‘the Many, or the Natural Democracy’.(4) Each of these passages, though differing in detail, derives from the threefold division into government by a single person, government by the few, and government by the many.  Consistently, Harrington warns that any state in which ‘the Many have predominant or exclusive power is bound to collapse into self-destructive anarchy: ‘a single  Council consisting of the Many, is ever tumultuous, and doth ill even while it means well’ [Hammersley : 113]. For this reason, his constitutional proposals, based on the principle of balance or separation of powers, gives the body of ‘the people’ a very limited voice—basically, a right to elect members of a popular assembly which itself could only vote yes or no on proposals submitted to it, without debate. Like Milton, who engaged in friendly debate with Harrington in The Readie and Easie Way, Harrington combined an unwavering commitment to the principle of popular sovereignty, the consent of the governed, with a deep scepticism about the ability of ‘the people’ to act rationally. Where Milton, like a number of other republican theorists, emphasised the role of virtuous citizens in a commonwealth, Harrington took a different approach. Convinced, like Machiavelli and Hobbes, that self-interest governed most human behaviour—‘a man doth not look upon reason as it is right or wrong in itself, but as it makes for him or against him’—Harrington looked for ways to limit the human propensity to pursue one’s own advantage at the expense of others.  Harrington’s constitutional proposals assume that no one is to be trusted, the one, the few, or the many: ‘Good orders make bad men good, and bad orders make good men bad’.

‘Give us good men and they will make us good laws’ is the maxim of a demagogue, and … exceeding fallible. But ‘give us good orders, and they will make us good men’ is the maxim of a legislator.(5)

 ______________________________

(1) Jonathan Scott, Commonwealth Principles : Republican Writing of the English Revolution. Cambridge: University Press, 2007 :  61. See J.G.A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment. Princeton: University Press, 1975; and James Harrington, The Commonwealth of Oceana and A System of Politics, ed. J.G.A. Pocock. Cambridge: University Press, 1992. 

(2) Walter Moyle, An Essay Upon the Constitution of the Roman Government (1726), in Hammersley : 97-98. On Harrington’s economic determinism, his conception of ‘economic change as a blind impersonal force’ bringing about historical change, see Christopher Hill, ‘James Harrington and the People’, in Puritanism and Revolution. London: Panther Books, 1968 : 301.

(3) Harrington, A System of Politics : 2.10, in Oceana, ed. Pocock : 271. 

(4) Henry Neville, Plato Redivivus (1681); Oceana; Harrington, Aphorisms Political (1659); and The Prerogative of Popular Government (1657-58), in Hammersley : 112-114. 

(5) Oceana, ed. Pocock : 22, 64; A System of Politics, 4. 22 : 274. On Harrington and Milton, see the excellent discussion in Scott, Commonwealth Principles : 181-184.

 

 

Cercles © 2020

All rights are reserved and no reproduction from this site for whatever purpose is permitted without the permission of the copyright owner.

Please contact us before using any material on this website.