Jacques
Derrida and the Humanities: A Critical Reader
Tom Cohen, ed.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
£47.50, 344 pages, ISBN 0521623707 (hardback).
£17.95, 344 pages, ISBN 0521625653 (paperback).
Thomas Dutoit
Université de Paris 7
Jacques Derrida and the Humanities: A Critical Reader: Did
this book necessarily have to be in English and published by a British
press aimed undoubtedly primarily at a North-American and British
readership? Could such a book have been in another language besides
English? And if so, which languages? Could it have been in French,
published in France? Independently of the question of the generic
phenomenon of the Critical Reader, proper to English-speaking
publishing, would the French title Jacques Derrida et les Humanités
be anything other than an incomprehensible calque, a nonsensical
imitation, which any teacher of an English-to-French translation course
would reject as such? In its title and its contents, why is Jacques
Derrida and the Humanities: A Critical Reader intrinsically inseparable
from the Anglo-American idiom, from the Anglo-American institution
of knowledge, notably the university? Why is Jacques Derrida and
the Humanities: A Critical Reader untranslatable into French,
be it into a direct equivalent of the French language or into the
French organization of tertiary education? Such are the questions
which give the pattern of this review.
Jacques Derrida and the Humanities must thus be situated within
the transformations of Anglo-Saxon tertiary education
systems, within those transformations of the human generally
speaking, and within (or without as the case may be) the French models
for tertiary education (i.e. the university versus all the other forms
of tertiary education). Although a version of this book is imaginable
in German coming out of Germany, in Japanese coming out of Japan,
to name two among other examples, a Jacques Derrida et les Humanités
coming out of France is much more difficult to imagine (even if three
of the contributors are French). In order to attain some semblance
of truth relative to its object, a review of this book needs also
to situate the conditions of possibility of Jacques Derrida and the
Humanities and Jacques Derrida and the Humanities.
Jacques Derrida and the Humanities is also to be comprehended
within a slew of publications, academic and non-academic, that intensified
in the late 1980s and throughout the 1990s, about the university especially
in North America.1 Derridas
numerous writings on this subject in particular2
consistently fuelled such writings, inspiring some and irritating
others. In France over the same time period, there has been, relatively
speaking, an audible silence in writings by academics about
the university and its place both among the other tertiary educational
apparatuses of France and within French society as a whole3.
While this claim about an audible silence echoes Alain
Renauts assessments of the relative indifference of French society,
and in particular of French academics inside and outside the university,
to its university system, this echoing of Renaut must also record
how Renaut himself silences the persistent calls from Derrida on this
subject, of which the speech by Derrida, The future of the profession,
included in Jacques Derrida and the Humanities, is the most
recent manifestation.4 For although
Alain Renauts early contribution to the examination of the university
system, in the form of his co-edited collection of translations of
founding essays from the early nineteenth century by Schelling, Fichte,
Schleiermacher, Humboldt and Hegel (Philosophies de luniversité.
LIdéalisme allemand et la question de luniversité5)
included an expression of gratitude from the young editors to Jacques
Derrida for encouraging the necessity of the undertaking prior to
its realization, Renaut makes no mention of Derridas writings
or actions about the university in his subsequent publications, notably
Les Révolutions de luniversité. Essai sur la
modernisation de la culture or caricatures them as a form of silence
itself in Que faire des universités ? The pertinence
of such symbolic patricide to Jacques Derrida and the Humanities:
A Critical Reader consists in how Renaut evinces surely one of
the most important sources of impact upon the Humanities (at the least,
in North America, but also elsewhere), namely the work of Derrida
and that in the wake of deconstruction widely understood
not as a method used by some literature professors,
but as a mutation in social values and arrangements, otherwise put,
as the historicity of history. It is surely ironic that the person
commissioned by the French government to write reports on the university
advocates some return to the Humanities yet occludes the possibility
that there might be a new Humanities, inchoate, nascent and to which
the syntagm Derrida and in Jacques Derrida and the
Humanities is germane. This does not mean that Derrida
is the guru or messiah which we must mystically follow, but rather
that deconstruction comprehends the major changes in society and elucidates
the foundations, often shaky, upon which our society is and has been
based. Such is the context of Jacques Derrida and the Humanities.
Jacques Derridas contribution, The future of the profession
or the university without condition (thanks to the Humanities,
what could take place tomorrow) magnificently sets up
a framework within which to consider the subsequent twelve essays
of the volume. For Derrida delivers a profession of faith [...]
in the University and, within the University, faith in the Humanities
of tomorrow (24) that helps those of us working in or with it
by clarifying how our work is doubly structured, in part by a respect
for tradition and precisely the tradition of unlimited commitment
to the truth (24), and in part by a regard towards the future
and especially towards what Derrida calls the event. Derrida
believes in the right to deconstruction as an unconditional
right to ask critical questions about the history of man, of
criticism, of questioning, of their authority, but also to the right
to do [so] affirmatively and performatively, that is, by producing
events, for example by writing, and by giving rise to singular oeuvres
(which up until now has been the purview of neither the classical
nor the modern Humanities). With the event of thought constituted
by such oeuvres, it would be a matter of making something happen
to this concept of truth or of humanity, without necessarily betraying
it (26). Event names something that changes the
notion of truth-as-masterable. Derrida wagers on the event.
With such an engagement, he commits to something completely different
from Alain Renaut, whose proposals for university education stop with
a tepid and blurred return to what he calls, but never defines, general
culture. Derrida on the contrary seeks not a return to something
known but takes risks for the future.
What such events might make happen to the concept of truth
is that truth not be defined as an affair of mastery and sovereignty
but rather as dependent upon an unconditional. Arguing against dogmatic
certainty and facile solutions that produced the problems we now have,
Derrida maintains that it would be necessary to dissociate a
certain unconditional independence of thought, of deconstruction,
of justice, of the Humanities, of the University, and so forth from
any phantasm of sovereign mastery (55). If we conceded to the
notion of the master (the teacher) as he (as she) who possesses certainty
and its conventions absolutely, then we first of all give in to a
phantasm, and secondly reduce the future to a mechanical application
of a program. Derridas allegiance to an unconditional independence
of thought resists such closure and finality by insisting upon what
never is mastered. As its etymology suggests, unconditional
is what cannot be agreed upon, what cannot be said, what is irreducible
to consensus. As teacher, what Derrida teaches is that without an
unteachable we cannot teach and are not teachers. The great difference
between Derrida and Renaut, between the proposals of the two most
important advocates of the university in France, is that whereas Renaut
calls for a return to an unproblematic general culture (he never problematizes
it and only advocates it because professionalized teaching fails),
Derrida on the contrary argues for a transformative reaction to tradition,
a re-activation that also produces something not only different but
as yet unconventional and moreover necessarily incomplete. The future
of the profession in the university without condition
is not about giving the possible, the pre-established. It is about
the fact that it does not and cannot give the answer. It can affirm
answers but it can never prove them as final solutions (I use this
term to denote the danger of the idea of the university as giving
answers as if they were final). This is, however, why the university
can always be appropriated: there is always someone claiming to have
the answer (27). The idea of the university is the commitment to the
unconditional: the incomplete, the impossibility of a simple truth,
truth as simple. This is why the university is permanently in danger:
first, such an avowal of powerlessness (which however is its invincible
force) is well-nigh an invitation to the wolves of demagogy,
capitalism and other simpletons; second, such an admission will be
understood as irresponsible by dogmatists. What is sovereign
for Derrida would be this unconditionality. It is what, by being impossible,
rules since our otherwise supposed sovereignty (mastery, control,
etc.) cannot overtake unconditionality.
Such is why Derrida equates the university and the humanities as the
place of irredentist resistance, and analogically as a principle of
civil disobedience. The university without condition, always in danger
of capitulating without conditions to all kinds of sources of appropriation,
should never be bought, never under foreign control. Derridas
political engagement to the humanities is to something that is not
to be overrun by reductive appropriations like capitalism or other
ideologies. The defense of the university without condition is like
the advocacy of recovery of lands of which one has been deprived,
but of lands which no one ever owns. No one owns deconstruction, either,
which is translated here into political theory, law, "gender
studies", art and aesthetics, literature, history, religion,
psychoanalysis.
Many of the essays in Jacques Derrida and the Humanities are
written by the greatest translators of Derrida into English (e.g.
Peggy Kamuf, David Wills, Geoffrey Bennington). As Derrida has noted
in private conversations, it is not accidental that his best readers
are also his translators. Translation is also fundamental to politics.
The relation of deconstruction to politics has long attracted the
curious. Deconstruction is understood from its earliest days, so to
speak, that is, from Derridas texts of the early 1960s,
as a translation of a tradition which transmits such tradition precisely
through a faithful-unfaithful translation. Translation in this sense
may be understood as what Bennington calls political responsibility
because it begins in the active, critical memory or reception
of an inheritance or a tradition which will remember us if we do not
remember it (197). Politics is no different from
any other of the concepts, traditions or practices which Derrida aims
to deconstruct so as not simply to let himself be played by them,
as if he were somebodys instrument. In Derrida, we find an
affirmation of the endlessness of politics, and thereby of freedom
(203), but it is freedom in a Kantian sense: it is because there is
no answer, no pre-established or even securely established way, that
we are free to act upon the basis of this lack. As a result, Derridas
work will not provide satisfying answers within readily identifiable
disciplinary boundaries, because those boundaries will ceaselessly
be moved by each successive intervention (197). Thus, deconstruction
works both prior to and after pre-determined categorizations and classifications:
There is no easy way to distinguish logical concerns from epistemological
ones in Derrida, nor these from ethical or political ones, simply
because Derrida is working at a level that precedes the establishment
of demarcations (197). The political gesture of Derrida might
be less to provide an answer than to keep open the possibility of
questions, for Derrida does not provide a theoretical model
for politics so much as it strives to keep open the event of alterity
which alone makes politics possible and inevitable, but which political
philosophy of all colors has always tried to close (207).
Among the points Derrida insists upon in his essay in this volume
is that the new Humanities in the university of tomorrow must take
on the questions of right and of law, both from within the Law School
and from outside it in the other departments and Schools of the university:
This new concept of the Humanities, even as it remains faithful
to its tradition, should include law, legal studies
(29). In many countries, this transformation has begun. The famous
Cardozo Law School conference on Deconstruction and Justice, from
1992, was one instance of many others in which there have been negotiations
between literature and law, law and history, law and psychoanalysis,
etc. It is worth insisting, yet again, that no significant collaboration
exists, in French universities, between, on the one hand, the departments
of letters, arts or sciences and, on the other, that of law (droit).
If one really wanted to imagine some forms such joint efforts could
take, and how Derrida has something to contribute on the point, looking
at Margaret Davies essay, Derrida and law: legitimate
fictions, will reveal several possibilities. Aside from the
common points with Derridas own essay (notably on what sovereignty
means in political theory), the reader will also find useful in Davies
piece her pitting what Derrida has to say about law and the idea according
to which there would be no law without an impure law or unlawful law
setting up pure law, against the paradox or uncertainty at the heart
of all law, according to which the law must be based on an extra-legal
fiction which legal theorists such as Hans Kelsen, H.L.A. Hart or
Tom Campbell develop. Thus, scholars coming to Derrida from law, but
also to law from the humanities, would do well to read this double
exposition. In an essay written in an exceptionally clear, user-friendly
prose requiring no prior knowledge of Derrida for it to be understandable,
Davies pulls no punches, for she highlights one of the central points
in Derrida, which is that the law as we know it is not ultimately
justifiable and that positive law masks its own violence
by reference to some justification which it can never find (227).
This situation is not to be ignored as if it didnt exist but
recognized as the condition of possibility of improving law or challenging
it, which deconstruction, or justice (as in Derridas formulation,
Deconstruction is justice), are synonymous with. Like
deconstruction, justice is of the law for both recognize
incessantly the violence of the law without which the law cannot make
itself either work or be obeyed, yet neither deconstruction nor justice
is reducible to law (233).
In the burgeoning field of gender studies, the name of
Judith Butler has perhaps become the reference. In her writings,
Butler moreover has always maintained a certain closeness to the work
of Derrida, a proximity which is yet another testimony of the extent
to which the title Jacques Derrida and the Humanities describes
a reality that can be understood practically as if it read Derrida
in (or across, or throughout) the Humanities.
Need we repeat that the same syntagm cannot be translated into
the French language, the French institution or the French society?
Professor of Comparative and French Literature, Peggy Kamuf tackles
the formidable question of gender and sexual difference
in Derridas writings, but also via a detour through the notion
of gender precisely in the work of Judith Butler. Derrida
and gender: the other sexual difference is thus an essay of
utmost importance for those working in gender studies.
As Kamuf notes and develops, gender itself doesnt
translate into French. It is not surprising, then, that the English
term as such does not appear in Derridas writings. As she wryly
but undeniably puts it, the expectation to talk about gender
limit[s] the choice of language in which one talks to
English. One can write gender only in English (82).
For linguistic, cultural and no doubt institutional reasons related
already to the possibility (or impossibility) of talking about Derrida,
work on gender does not happen in the same way everywhere. Kamuf reads
Butler closely, arguing (against common opinion regarding Butlers
discourse) that Butler reinscribes the sex and gender
opposition which she, Butler, had been trying to displace. The effect
of Butlers discourse, Kamuf persuasively shows, is that it re-installs
the traditional opposition. In Kamufs words, the collapse
of the discourse of sex/ gender depends on the language
of sex and gender upholding the distinction
against collapse (84). Discourse would be to language
what a primary production would be to a secondary inscription. Butler
remains metaphysical because she grants priority to a notion of discourse,
to a Foucauldian apparatus of production, making inscription
secondary. Kamuf moves then to the deconstructor of metaphysics, Derrida,
and the many threads of sexuality throughout his work,
not all of which go by the names, even translated, for sex
and gender. As with almost all the essays in this volume,
what follows is an extremely clear and exact reading and exposition
of Derridas thought, or writing, on the question: in this case,
his several essays on Geschlecht (sex, gender, race, etc.)
in Heidegger. What ensues is how sex and gender
are inscribed in a network of terms (power, powerlessness, impotency,
etc.) where one cannot arrest either term.
Related most to the contributions of Kamuf, Bennington and Davies,
is Hent de Vriess Derrida and ethics: hospitable thought.
Establishing with clarity the dense nexus within which Derridas
numerous works on politics, religion, ethics, law, and justice move
(in particular those devoted to Immanuel Kant and Emmanuel Levinas),
de Vries elucidates the relation of responsibility and hospitality
running through close to forty years of publications. This relation
is grasped in terms first of what de Vries suggests is Derridas
single most wide-ranging insight, namely infinite
responsibility and its necessary betrayal in repetition
(173) and second of the two regimes of one law of hospitality
(191), that is, as absolute idea and as concrete example. Both terms,
responsibility and hospitality, are double, each constituted by differance
as the irreducible tension between idealism and pragmatism. Although
such a tension may sound abstract, de Vries shows how, for Derrida,
such tension is not only what structures philosophical discussions
of an array of geo-political subjects like citizenship and immigration,
but also our everyday dealings and negociations, experience
in general (191).
Another intersection at which Derridas work has often been operative
has been that between science and religion, between technology and
faith. One of the most important lessons one can receive from Derrida
may be his deconstruction of these seeming opposites. It belongs to
common sense (indeed common sense may be nothing other than this)
that science and religion, modern technology and archaic faith, are
mutually exclusive or at any rate simply incompatible. To read Derrida
is to re-assess such doxa. No student of nineteenth century
Britain or United States, be she in history or literature, ought to
be able to ignore Derridas reading of the twisted-together development
of science and religion. Bernard Stieglers arduous Derrida
and technology: fidelity at the limits of deconstruction and the prosthesis
of faith overviews these two threads from the earliest to the
most recent writings, arguing that faith and tele-technology
are [...] mutually insoluble and mutually inseparable. Steigler
shows that deconstruction is both a thinking of technology and of
fidelity to the past, notably a thinking of religion. These are two
such dissociated domains in the contemporary world, at a superficial,
commonsensical level, that it is difficult to imagine much communication
between the Science faculty and the Theology faculty (and in the French
university in particular, the Theology faculty having disappeared
shortly after the Revolution). Jacques Derrida and the Humanities
however is not only the name of a book published by Cambridge University
Press, but of a network of interactions that happen in many places,
notably universities, of the world.
Other disciplines and Schools or Faculties
are convened in Jacques Derrida and the Humanities. Philosophy,
rather disappointingly, by Christopher Fynsk in Derrida and
philosophy: acts of engagement. And historians might be disturbed,
or emboldened, by Peter Fenvess exploration, in Derrida
and history: some questions Derrida pursues in his early writings,
of an early statement in Derrida according to which Astonishment,
rather, by language, that is, by historicity, is taken as
the origin of history. As Fenves restates it, historicity, language[,]
inaugurates history (272). This claim ought to allure historians.
Focusing on the archaeological history of madness in Foucault studied
in Derridas essay, Cogito and the History of Madness
(1963), and on the teleological history of reason examined in Derridas
Introduction (1962) to Edmund Husserls Origin of Geometry,
Fenves returns us to that curious sentence, even though Fenves does
not quote it, from Derrida, Sil y a une histoire,
lhistoricité ne peut donc être que le passage dune
Parole, la tradition pure dun Logos originaire vers un Telos
polaire (Introduction 165). Historicity would be the
passage of speech (tra-dition) from beginning to end, if there
is history, a history. Yet, Derrida calls historicity
the primordial double motion forwards and backwards without which
there would be no history. In short, I only have a history insofar
as I both have memories and traces, conscious and unconscious,
of who I was previously, and become different by new
experiences. This is not a simple linear process; in fact, it is constantly
zigzagging recession and procession, such that my history,
the result of the possibility of such double motion, is constantly
changing, is multiple as opposed to simple, oscillating and spiraling
as opposed to linear. When Derrida italicizes the condition of a linear
movement through time, the condition is that there be one history.
The double movement of historicity however tells of a repeating and
new history, more than one, that is fundamentally also indistinguishable
from story (histoire). Without such movement, no history
would be possible (Introduction 58, my translation).
It is interesting to note that the two contributors from France excepting
Derrida, Stiegler and René Major, work in the fields of philosophy
and psychoanalysis, the two longest-standing theoretical paradigms,
if you will, within which Derrida, since the early 1950s, has worked
(literature is the other). René Majors
Derrida and psychoanalysis: desistantial psychoanalysis
is structured in two large parts both of which will interest anyone
working on the intersection of literature and psychoanalysis. A first
development re-visits many of Derridas essays on psychoanalysis,
showing how, even if Freudian concepts belong to the history of metaphysics
which Derrida seeks to deconstruct, many of the Freudian concepts
(the unconscious, pleasure/ pain, subject/ object, present/ past,
delay, etc.) remain active in Derrida, in particular in how Derrida
interrogates writing. Major isolates the core of the disagreement
between Derrida and Lacan, namely deconstruction as divisibility,
and devotes the rest of his article to an in-depth study of how Derridas
reading of psychoanalysis requires modifications in clinical, theoretical
and institutional aspects of psychoanalysis, in particular aspects
of the Lacanian legacy. These modifications involve what Derrida and
Major call désistance, which itself involves
among other things a disidentification from every position in
estance, from all determinations of the subject by the ego
(301). Major details especially Lacans reading of Poe. It is
Lacans identification with one of the protagonists
in a scene of inheritance of thought that reveals the blind spot of
the interpretation or the fixation to a demand for meaning (310).
In short, Major equips us with new ways of understanding the disagreement
between Derrida and Lacan about whether the letter must always arrive
at its destination (Lacan) or may not (Derrida).
New Zealander working in the States, literature professor David Wills
returns to Derridas La vérité en peinture
[1978] to explore Derridas version of aesthetics
in Derrida and aesthetics: Lemming (reframing the abyss).6
In doing so, Wills has recourse to the notion of iterability: If
one were to posit anything like an architectonics of Derridean philosophical
discourse, one would have to argue that whether it is a matter of
aesthetics, politics or ethics, access to it is consistently articulated
across this threshold concept of the trait as a function of iterability
(119). Extending Jacques Derrida and the Humanities into the
realm of aesthetics and art criticism by visualizing Derridas
figural graphism, his painterly writing, the brilliant part
of Wills contribution to this volume consists in how he shows
such iterability to be coextensive with reversibility, which Wills
calls the anagrammatical effect of iterability, by means
of which every utterance, in being repeated, is resituated, recontextualized,
and rearranged (121). Now, Wills essay is crucial reading
for those wanting to understand better the principles of inversion
throughout Derridas writing. Inversion is central to what Derrida
calls différance, namely the way a particular hierarchical
opposition would not exist were its inverse not to be recognized by
suppression. Yet most important is how Wills shows Derridas
inversion of philosophical discourse on art (Kants): the frame,
, of art
which Kant excluded from his aesthetics collapses inward such that
any inside of a painting or art object is traversed by crossing lines,
by an X or by a +. From Derridas deconstruction
of traditional art criticism, Wills moves fascinatingly to an exposition
of the graphic effect of the archaic diacritical marks appearing in
Derridas text. This essay therefore serves a triple purpose:
the relation of deconstruction to the arts, writing as visual art,
and iterability as anagrammatization, are each clearly presented.
As his title indicates, J. Hillis Millers Derrida and
literature reads how Derrida reads literature. This essay is
important for literary critics, for littéraires. Miller
is the only contributor from the United States or Great Britain writing
about his own academic discipline, but to do so entails understanding
what literature is to this particular philosopher and the problem
it poses to philosophy in general. Prior to his highlighting how Derrida
reads literary texts themselves, Miller returns to where Derrida defines
literature, notably in the interview with Derek Attridge, This
Strange Institution Called Literature: Literature is for
Derrida the possibility for any utterance, writing, or mark to be
iterated in innumerable contexts and to function in the absence of
identifiable speaker, context, reference, or hearer (59). That
is, literature is the possibility that any seemingly non-literary
usage of language can be used in a literary way, that any literal
use of language can always be taken figuratively, such that figurative
meaning is the basis upon which literal meaning stands. Yet what we
identify as literary is the result of certain rules, conventions and
institutions. Derrida moreover identifies literature, as an institution
in the West, with democracy and freedom of speech. With this notion
of literature, democracy and freedom of speech presuppose not only
the authority to say everything but also to disclaim responsibility
for what is said. Miller here reconstructs dense passages from Derridas
essay Passions to postulate, Literature is an exploitation
of the possibility that any utterance may be non-serious
(65). Among the implications of such a statement probed by Miller
is the idea that literature, and therefore all writing, is always
a reduction of an idea (a truth, the notion of serious linguistic
usage, the right way to think, my real intention).
Yet such an idea may always only be a supposition, radically unverifiable,
because the only sensible form it takes is its appearance in literature,
in language as literary. All language is potentially non-serious,
potentially just literature, because it never is for sure the restitution
of the serious, of something prior to language. This way
in which literature is radical non-responsibilityas in the disclaimer
of movies, any resemblance to real persons, living or dead,
is purely coincidentalis the correlative of literature
as freedom of speech, the right to say everything, linchpin of democracy.
Derridas essay appears in English translation, but its translator
is not mentioned. She happens to be Peggy Kamuf. It is unfortunate
the book omits this information, as well as any biographical information
on the contributors, whose institutional affiliations for those in
the know reveal aspects of the book not available to the general reader.
It seems that this book fails an entry-level question, for in it Derridas
essay stresses the importance of the study by the university
of the university, and thus of the importance of institutions
and positions, yet the book apparently forgets any mention of institutions
or positions. Even if naming institutions and positions can sometimes
amount to name-dropping, the solution to that risk need not be omission
(if it were, the title page of the volume would not identify the editors
affiliation). This reviewer happens to know the disciplinary and institutional
affiliations of many of the contributors to this volume: working in
departments of English, Comparative Literature, French, German, Philosophy,
the writers here are university professors in the Netherlands, Great
Britain, the United States and France, although at least one is not
a university professor but rather a practicing psychoanalyst. Interestingly,
the contributors from Great Britain and the United States tend to
work in national or comparative literature departments (Tom Cohen,
J. Hillis Miller, Peggy Kamuf, David Wills, Peter Fenves, Geoff Bennington),
even when writing primarily philosophy (Bennington, Fenves, Christopher
Fynsk), whereas the contributors from France are from either philosophy
departments or the profession of psychoanalysis (Bernard Stiegler,
René Major). Let us leave here Hent de Vries aside, who works
more or less out of a philosophy department in the Netherlands. It
is not an accident that the psychoanalyst and philosopher come from
France, yet none of the literature professors. It would be wrong to
assign to this formation of contributors a determinism (there are
literature professors in France who could and do write about Derrida,
and there are psychoanalysts and philosophers in the U.S. working
on Derrida). Still, the distribution of roles in this volume does
reflect the somewhat true yet simplistic schematization of the university
which I am trying to spotlight here. The book, by omitting any institutional,
biographical or disciplinary affiliation, obscures precisely an essential
point of a book such as this one particularly, the point being that
there is relation between what one writes and where one writes it
from, even if this relation is not governed by determinism. Although
a reviewer could content himself with simply resuming what the essays
in this volume say, it is incumbent upon at least this one to stress
that part of what these essays and this volume say is inseparable
from the contexts of that saying. From Derridas Introduction
to Edmund Husserls LOrigine de la géométrie
through his activism for the teaching of philosophy during the 1970s
to the seminars on nationalism and institutions in the late 1980s
through the many texts on the organization of education in Du droit
à la philosophie and beyond to LUniversité
sans condition [2001] (of which the English translation, presented
upon invitation to Stanford University in 1998, is published in this
volume), institutional awareness is one of the most constant impulses
throughout his oeuvre. To note the institutional affiliations
of the contributors (and translators) is to recognize the inherently
foreign status of this book; indeed, there is something structurally
foreign, from the point of view of the French context, about both
Jacques Derrida and the Humanities, as well
as about the and that joins them: the Humanities
do not exist in the French university system as the place where a
student studies several of its disciplines all the while specializing
in one nor do the Humanities exist nominally in France
(the term sciences humaines or lettres
are the recent and less recent terms used); Jacques Derrida
has been difficult to classify, even if he has been prominent in the
French intellectual scene for forty years; and the and
joining Jacques Derrida and the Humanities is anything
but granted in France, where, because of the lack of a coherence,
of adherence, across disciplines in particular in the intellectual
itinerary of university students, the Humanities cannot
be said to exist except as atomized entities therefore not coherent
in any whole, in any university, so that it becomes doubly
incoherent to join by an and two separate fields both
of which are by definition pluri-disciplinary (Derrida works in, and
is worked on by, many fieldsliterature, history, psychoanalysis,
music, the visual and performing arts, etc. all of which can be found
inside as well as outside the Anglo-American university; an education
there in the Humanities will be built from courses in
different disciplines some of which possibly from outside the Humanities).
Despite the drawback of these omissions, Jacques Derrida and the
Humanities: A Critical Reader is excellent for its polymathic
and polymorphic comprehension of Derridas work, and of its interactions
with the different disciplines of the contemporary university according
to the Anglo-Saxon model.
1
Among the many are Samuel Weber, Institution and Interpretation
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), Bill Readings,
The University in Ruins (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1996), and Peggy Kamuf, The Division of Literature or the University
in Deconstruction (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997).
2
Especially in his Du droit à la philosophie (Paris :
Galilée, 1990).
3
There are obvious exceptions, from Emile Durkheim to Pierre
Bourdieu and Jean-Claude Passeron, not to mention Derrida.
4
Les Révolutions de luniversité. Essai
sur la modernisation de la culture (Paris: Calmann-Lévy,
1995). Que faire des universités (Paris: Bayard, 2002).
As in his government report at < http://www.education.gouv.fr/rapport/renaut/default.htm>,
these essays accurately analyze the numerous weaknesses leading to
the implosion of the French university, and they argue for a restoration,
in the university, of culture générale
or liberal arts education descendant from the Humanities.
5
Translated by J.-F. Courtine, L. Ferry, A. Laks, A. Renaut
and J. Rivelaygue, with a preface by Ferry, Renaut and J.-P. Pesron
(Paris: Payot, 1980).
6
Jacques Derrida and the Humanities includes another
foray into artistic representation, with Marian Hobsons Derrida
and representation: mimesis, presentation, and representation.