Back
to Book Reviews
Back to Cercles
|
‘Paradise Lost’ and the Republican Tradition from Aristotle to Machiavelli
William Walker
Turnhout / Tournai : Brepols, 2009
Cursor Mundi Series, vol. 6. Hardback.
xii+332 p. 70 €
ISBN: 978-2-503-52877-9 Reviewed by Freyja Cox Jensen
Christ Church, Oxford
William Walker’s
‘Paradise Lost’ and the Republican Tradition
from Aristotle to Machiavelli boldly sallies forth into the battleground of
republicanism and the classics in the seventeenth century. In demonstrating how
Paradise Lost relates to the dominant
ideas within the tradition, Walker takes arms
against a sea of historians and literary critics who have sought to claim Milton’s poem as “an
expression of his commitment to English republicanism” [1]. Walker sees Paradise Lost as primarily a work of
heterodox Protestant ideology, which, he argues, Milton “presents as being incompatible with
both ancient and Machiavellian republicanism” [8].
This rather
controversial thesis is presented in a clear, thorough and logical manner over
five self-contained chapters. These provide a framework for Walker’s analysis, each dealing with one of what
the author considers to be the key components of the republican tradition:
human nature, virtue, forms of government, civil liberty, and history. In every
chapter, Walker
first examines how the chief authors of the tradition present the idea, before
considering how it is addressed Paradise
Lost. As a method, it is not the most elegant, but it is admirably easy to
follow. Indeed, much of the book’s not inconsiderable value lies in the clarity
with which Walker
explains his interpretation of the fraught term, ‘republican’. Given the problematic
nature of republicanism in early modern scholarship, where republican and
‘neo-Roman’ discourses are discerned and discussed from a wide variety of
positions, it is refreshing to see so direct a response to the problems of
defining exactly what is understood by these terms.
Walker’s ideas
about what it means to be republican are sometimes idiosyncratic, but are
firmly based on common sense and satisfyingly located within their original
classical context. By going ad fontes,
Walker displays
a sensitive appreciation of the complexities of the ancient world and its
writers, the texts which comprise the ‘classics’ and the authors whose works
become the ‘republican tradition’. His treatment of the classical sources is
painstaking, and although he confesses to giving “what may seem to some to be
an excessive amount of attention to Aristotle, Polybius, Cicero, Sallust, Livy
and Machiavelli”, this is by no means a problem [9]. Such an overview is
crucial if the reader is to locate Walker’s understanding of ‘republicanism’ in
any meaningful context; indeed, if I have a criticism of this part of the book,
it is that I would have liked to see more
attention given to some of the complexities of the political thought of the
ancient authors. I wonder, for example, whether it is really possible to do
justice to Cicero’s views on human nature in slightly under seven pages, or to
his political thought more generally without an index entry for ‘scepticism’.
“It is reasonable and
fruitful to think of the republican tradition as a family”, we are told, and
this is a subtle conceit which allows for the varying degrees of
(dis)agreement between the authors [293]. Unquestionably, the six chosen by Walker deserve a
place in the ‘republican family’ he constructs, but so do others, and Walker
admits that it would be interesting to see how a consideration of authors such
as Plutarch or the medieval political theorists could modify some of his
conclusions [300]. Similarly, there is
little exploration of the changing reception of the authors’ ideas, or how they
might be read from different perspectives, at the time of composition, in Milton’s time, and at any
point in between. Walker himself pre-empts another main point of criticism,
acknowledging that the way in which he has explored ideas of republicanism does
not fully show how the writers in the tradition engage with and inform each
other [299].
But these qualms aside, the reader will find in this
monograph a redefinition of what the words ‘republican tradition’ actually
mean. Given the vehemence
of arguments on the topic of republicanism, this is no small contribution to
the field. And after all, Walker
does not seek to provide a comprehensive analysis of the philosophy of the
various authors whose work he explores; he simply wants to clarify the grounds
on which his arguments concerning Paradise
Lost rest. His main aim is to present a reassessment of Milton’s
epic, reclaiming his heterodox Protestantism as the dominant influence upon the
work, and historicising “in a way that does not favour the socio-political at
the expense of the religious” [311].
Walker finds the abiding question
of why the politics of Paradise Lost
differ from those espoused in the prose works to be easily answered, because he
has redefined what republican politics are. Paradise
Lost represents a break with the traditions that inform Milton’s prose. The poem is written in a
different context, for a different purpose, and therefore Milton assumes a different voice. Walker
moderates Worden’s suggestion that the work is purely one of faith – he certainly
believes that it engages with political issues – but agrees that it is not a
work in the republican tradition [306]. In short, when he writes Paradise Lost, Milton’s cause is no
longer that of the ‘English Republicanism’ of the 1650s, grounded
in the philosophy of the ancients; therefore the work in no way reaffirms the
ideologies of the commonwealth men [306, 2]. For Walker, although Paradise Lost explores some of the same
ideas about “politics very broadly conceived” as do the republican authors, Paradise Lost is “merely a distant relative
in the republican family at best, and a hostile one at that” [14, 301].
Indeed, for Walker, Paradise Lost is, in many ways,
explicitly ‘anti-classical’, in that it breaks conclusively from the tradition
of Aristotle and Cicero. It is therefore not ‘republican’ in any of the ways scholars
have previously sought to define it. Walker sees Milton consciously repudiating the ancients
and working with a clearly heterodox Protestant vision of the world. Nor is
this rejection of the pagan, ‘republican’ authors incidental, but “the disagreements are
fundamental and systematic” [305]. Israel, not Rome,
is Milton’s
template, and Paradise Lost is more
Christian than classical. The Milton of Paradise
Lost is a “heterodox Protestant who has stopped trying to incorporate, or
make it appear as though it is possible to incorporate, the major ancient pagan
teachings about the ends of man with his religious faith” [306].
Despite
the firmly-stated conclusion, this is not a book about the Protestant nature of
Paradise Lost. Nor is it really about
Paradise Lost and the tradition of
republican thinking, or neo-Roman politics. It is a book about republicanism
and the various meanings this term might have in the field of early modern
studies, combined with an exposition of why this is nothing to do with Paradise Lost. In fact, Paradise Lost almost appears to be of secondary concern… But this
is not to say that the work is in any way inadequate. Far from it. This is an
important contribution to a dense and involved area, and in its open and unapologetic
redefinition of a perennially problematic theme, it is a breath of fresh air in
a crowded, heated debating chamber.
Cercles © 2011
All rights are reserved and no reproduction from this site for whatever
purpose is permitted without the permission of the
copyright owner. Please contact us before using any
material on this website.
|
|