Space in Language and Cognition : Explorations in Cognitive Diversity Language, Culture & Cognition 5, Cambridge University Press, 2003
Reviewed by Yvon Keromnes
The relation between language and thought is a long-standing problem, one which has been regularly tackled by philosophers, later by psychologists, anthropologists and linguists as well and which, to this day, has failed to meet a satisfying answer. S. Levinson’s monograph Space in Language and Cognition (henceforth SILC) is about the relation between language and spatial cognition, and is more precisely concerned with the frames of reference commonly used in spatial language and thinking. The crucial importance of spatial thinking in our cognition is evidenced, for instance, by the widespread use of spatial metaphors in everyday language (see Lakoff & Johnson, 1980), and the author’s hypothesis as to the reason of this importance is that spatial cognition may be [xvii] “the evolutionary earliest domain of systematic cross-modal cognition,” i.e. a domain combining information from different sources (visual, auditory, proprioceptive, kinesthetic, equilibrium, olfactory) into spatial representations that must correlate to some extent. The question about frames of reference can be illustrated by the two readings of such statements as “the cat is behind the truck,” corresponding to two distinct mental representations, i.e. that of a cat on the other side of the truck from the viewer’s standpoint, or that of a cat at the rear-end of the truck. The spatial framework yielding the first reading will sometimes be called deictic, the second intrinsic. The thesis presented in SILC, as stated in the “blurb” (and in somewhat more cautious terms inside the book) is that “even in a core cognitive domain such as spatial thinking, language influences how people think, memorize and reason about spatial relations and directions.” This argument in favour of a “Whorfian” effect of language on spatial cognition (the so-called “linguistic determinism” thesis) together with the observation [xix] that “different human groups use different spatial frameworks,” for instance absolute frameworks (e.g. “there’s an ant north of your foot!”) goes against most cognitive literature, in which, until now, space has been regarded as possibly the strongest candidate for a cognitive universal. SILC contains a short preface and seven chapters. The first introductory chapter gives a brief outline of Western ideas on spatial thinking, from Plato’s materialistic view of air as a substance with geometrical properties, Aristotle’s view of space as a nested series of places, to Newton’s distinction between absolute and relative space (taking up Plato), confirmed by Kant’s discovery of enantiomorphs (the paradoxical relation between two gloves in a pair, exactly similar yet not interchangeable), which in turn lead to the egocentric and anthropomorphic view on human spatial thinking prevalent today, the notion [11] that “spatial coordinates are derived from the planes though our body, giving left and right, front and back, up and down as the primary planes”; these egocentric and anthropomorphic characteristics are widely assumed to be universal, and this, in Levinson’s view [14], “is a major ethnocentric error.” Instead, SILC [22] proposes to show that “there is diversity in cognition just as there is diversity in language, clothing, hairstyle, kinship practices, modes of subsistence, ritual and religion.” The second chapter presents different frames of reference used by humans while reviewing the concepts used in variously combined oppositions to describe these frames of reference in differing fields (e.g. “egocentric” vs. “allocentric” or “viewer-centred” vs. “object-centred” vs. “environment-centred”) as well as the linguistic expression of these frames of reference in a cross-linguistic perspective. In that respect, Levinson [34] remarks that “the analysis of spatial terms in familiar European languages remains deeply confused, and those in other languages almost entirely unexplored,” and he goes on to propose a ternary typology, “intrinsic,” “relative” and “absolute,” each of these categories comprising several related yet semantically distinct subcategories. This typology is based on the work of the Language and Cognition Group at the Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics in Nijmegen (headed by S. Levinson) on [xix] “over forty, mostly unwritten languages spoken in small-scale, traditional societies.” The three linguistic frames of reference are then distinguished according to a number of parameters, and aligned according to the concepts previously reviewed, which leads Levinson to take up Molyneux’s question to Newton (if a blind man, who knew by touch the difference between a cube and a sphere, had his sight restored, would he recognize the selfsame objects under his new perceptual modality or not?). The conclusion offered in SILC is that if frames of reference are not entirely translatable from one to the other, then “representational systems of different kinds, specialized to different sensory modalities (like visual memory) or output systems (like gesture and language), may be capable of adopting different frames of reference” [60]; i.e. the answer is “yes.” Chapter three deals with linguistic diversity in a survey that is not exhaustive (such an exhaustive survey is presented, along with its methodology, in a companion book, Grammars of Space, Levinson & Wilkins, 2006) but offers enough evidence of radical differences in this respect to show, in the author’s opinion [111], “that the assumption of uniformity [in spatial semantics] is entirely mistaken.” This is illustrated, in particular, by the fact that some frames of reference are prevalent in certain languages and not in others; but frames of reference are here studied in a wider approach of spatial semantics, along with location systems in which no frame of reference is used, placenames (where the figure is located at a named place/ground), deixis (where the figure is located relative to the ground) and topology (where the figure is located as contiguous to the ground), and motion. Consideration is given to the respective advantages and disadvantages of the different systems. The simplest system, naming the location, is very well for underpopulated areas, but would be cognitively too costly elsewhere. In most cases, deixis crucially lacks angular specifications, so that [70] “deictics are often (and often obligatorily) accompanied by gesture.” Topology also involves a loss of information regarding angular and distance specifications, but may come first in language acquisition. It has also been shown that in many languages, some prepositions and adverbs used in frames of reference originate in topological notions, as in the English “back,” first designating a body part, then a part of an object, then the space contiguous to that part, and eventually the space behind it [106]. As for spatial systems involving frames of reference, the greater complexity of (ternary) relative systems compared to (binary) intrinsic ones raises the question of the reason why languages would develop the former. The answer offered in SILC is threefold. Chapter four gives us some insight into the “cognitive style” of two so-called “absolute communities,” speakers of Guugu Yimithirr (an Australian language, henceforth GY) and of Tzeltal (a Mayan language) and investigates the hypothesis that non-verbal cognition might evidence characteristics similar to those of the languages spoken in these communities. In order to study non-verbal cognition (mostly spatial memory), special tests have been devised, which are presented in some detail in this chapter. GY is a language almost completely absolute in spatial description, with the exception of [120] “a few body-part terms which have slightly extended spatial uses, for example walu (temple), baaru (front), buthiil (nose), all used to indicate the front of a man or animal, usually in conjunction with an orientational specification by cardinal direction.” GY makes essential use of cardinal directions, which actually refer to quadrants (or edges). This is somewhat misleading, because what in SILC is glossed as “north” seems to really mean “somewhere approximately between north-west and north-east.” The orientational terms appear in various derivations to constitute a remarkably detailed absolute system. Also remarkable is the absence of relative terms. There is, for example, no spatial term for “right” or “left.” Not surprisingly, GY speakers seem to keep constant track of their bearings and are impressively able to point immediately to known locations in various circumstances [127]. Levinson has tested the coding of visual perception in GY speakers using, in particular, what he calls the “rotation paradigm,” a test he designed himself in 1992: if, facing north, a subject is asked to remember the picture of an arrow pointing to the right, hence to the east, and the subject is then made to turn round 180° to face a similar table, a “relative coder” will show an arrow pointing right, whereas an “absolute coder” will show an arrow pointing left (and still pointing east). The results of several experiments seem to show a majority of “absolute coders” in that community. Tzeltal possesses both intrinsic terms and absolute terms, but the only absolute orientation is on the north-south axis. East and west are both glossed as “across.” Members of the Tenejapan community, who speak Tzeltal, also tend to show a surprising incapacity at distinguishing between images which are symmetrical on a vertical axis, and this, it seems, independently of cardinal orientation. And a majority of the Tzeltal speakers tested seem to be “absolute coders.” From these results, SILC concludes that there is the possibility of a “Whorfian effect” in the relation between language and cognition. Chapter six investigates the cognition of navigation. The literature on animal navigation is very large, but we know very little about the human cognitive aspects involved in wayfinding. One major aspect of the problem, though, is that [218] “human groups vary enormously in their navigational systems and abilities: navigation is quite largely a cultural matter.” One cannot, therefore, talk of human navigation in quite the same way as one would talk of the salmon’s or the stork’s navigations. The point, here again, is to show a correlation between the characteristics of a given language and the navigational abilities of its speakers, and the working hypothesis is that [227] “speakers of absolute-coding languages should be better dead reckoners,” a fact that the reader will accept readily, as this ability has already been presented as characteristic of GY and Tzeltal speakers (see chapter four). But this study on three absolute communities, GY, Tenejapan (Tzeltal speakers) and Hai///om bushmen compared to two relative communities (Dutch and English) seems to be the first systematic study on the subject. And, as expected, the results of this study show that people in absolute communities are markedly better at pointing toward a specific location than people belonging to relative communities (although there are some differences in the degree of accuracy in different absolute communities, Tzeltal speakers are not as good dead reckoners as the other two communities). Also under investigation in this chapter are gestures made by speakers of absolute and relative communities. The outcome is that there seems to be a typical gesture system in the former, which includes for instance large gestures with extended arms, the frequent use of both hands, and pointing behind oneself and through oneself, the speaker’s trunk remaining mostly stable through sequences of gestures. This leads the author to infer the use of absolute mental maps by these speakers, as opposed to so-called “strip maps” by relative speakers. In the final chapter, the author attempts to elaborate a model of the human mind’s representational system drawn from the observations presented in the preceding chapters. The main point is that there cannot be a single spatial representation in the mind, there must be many different representations, e.g. visual imagery, mental maps and propositional representation. Absolute and relative orientation for instance, which can coexist, imply two different kinds of representations that are not directly translatable into one another. The implications of all this are described as “Whorfian perspectives” but the theory as such [301] “is not Whorfian in any strict sense.” The main argument is that (ibid.) “language is an output system. The output must meet the local semantic requirements. Consequently, the input to language production must code for the right distinctions.” And therefore [302], “semantic parameters are not universal.” To account for the possibility of universals (the three spatial frames of reference seem to be such universals) and what is described in SILC as a variety of cognitive styles, the author presents in the last section of this chapter his “co-evolution hypothesis.” According to this theory, already envisaged by biologists R. Dawkins and J. Thompson, and anthropologist D. Sperber [319], “both genome and culture are conceived of as vertically transmitted lines of self-replicating and modifying information, which interact with one another in systematic ways.” Assessment: the overall impression given by SILC is that of a rich, complex, and thought-provoking book. As an interdisciplinary work, it reaches significantly beyond the scope of cognitive linguistics, convincingly calling up theoretical resources from anthropology, biology, philosophy and psychology. Every point is discussed in detail and taken up from various angles (except, understandably, for the concluding hypothesis); this richness and complexity also has its downside, as it entails a certain amount of repetitiveness, and, sometimes, backward logic. Something presented as established, e.g. that ([218] “one cannot talk of human navigation in the same breath as one might talk of the navigation of the arctic tern” will often be taken up later as mere conjecture, as in the mention of observations [241] “rendering talk of a single uniform kind of basic human navigation suspect.”
Cercles©2007
|
|