Elizabeth
Clark, History, Theory, Text: Historians
and the Linguistic Turn (Cambridge MA: Harvard
University Press, 2004, $19.95, 336 pages, ISBN 0674015843)—Kristen
Chamberland, California State University - Long Beach
Elizabeth Clark’s History, Theory, Text: Historians
and the Linguistic Turn is a brave and fascinating
undertaking. The first seven chapters of her book are
devoted to a concise, yet extremely thorough account
of the theoretical tug-of-war between nineteenth and
twentieth-century philosophers and historians. In these
chapters, Clark aptly traces the sometimes parallel,
yet often contradictory development of philosophy and
history in the past two centuries, attending equally
to both fields. She demonstrates the points at which
the two disciplines intersect, and the points at which
they seem to be running in completely opposite directions.
Then, her concluding chapter outlines her arguments
for the value of philosophical theory in history, and
the ways in which it is particularly useful for premodern
historians. This book enters the discussion of professional
historians in an attempt to quell the “death knell”
that some of her fellow historical scholars are sounding
for their discipline [1]. Rather than taking the attacks
upon history by philosophers as fatal assaults, she
strives to absorb and consider the critiques and suggestions
of other disciplines, in order to strengthen her own
field.
In
her first chapter, Clark explicates nineteenth-century
professional historians’ obsession with objectivity.
Taking their cues from the increasingly respected natural
sciences and medicine, nineteenth-century historians—Germans
especially—strove to write history “as it actually happened”
by using documents in a “scientific” manner, thus making
history transparent, and eschewing the notion of interpretation
(here Clark is referring to Ranke’s 1885 most oft-quoted
phrase, “Wie es eigentlich gewesen,” from 1885’s Geschichten
der romanishchen und germanischen Volker von 1494 bis
1514). Though these methods were extremely pervasive,
Clark does assert that there were critics, even during
its heyday, who rejected the positivism of Rankean history,
as well as pointing out that even the selection of documents
by historians signals their judgment and interpretation.
It
is in this chapter that she introduces the epistemological
problem that plagues all historians, the problem that
she will return to again and again in subsequent chapters:
Since it is the historian who offers
explanations for events, posits causes and effects,
fills in the gaps of and provides meaning to the historical
record, how is the truth of an account to be assessed?
Should or should not the historian strive to align
“the structure of his interpretation” with “the structure
of factuality” [25].
She
explains that most historians have not attempted to
wrestle with the real implications of this problem,
claiming that even the most notable twentieth-century
schools of history “retained traditional, and largely
unexamined epistemological assumptions” [25]. Clark
gives a few reasons for this, citing a lingering appeal
to objectivism and a fear of philosophical debate. As
a result, since the early 1970s historians have been
under siege, claims Clark, the same mêlée
that has ravaged all scholars of the humanities, due
to that wrecking ball known as Theory. However, Clark,
quoting Beverly Southgate, astutely asks, “Why should
the call for historians to set forth more explicitly
the philosophical underpinnings of their subject constitute
a particularly threatening assignment?” [27] With this
refusal to declare the death of history, she sets the
tone for the account to follow.
In
Chapter 3, Clark argues that structuralism has challenged
history in useful ways, though it often seemed anti-historical
to those scholars defending their field. Their defensiveness
is understandable; philosophers such as Dusse declared
war on historicism, historical context, and the search
for origins. Claude Levi-Strauss, one of the founders
of structuralism, “condemned” the entire historical
disciple as myth. However, Clark reaches beyond these
affronts to show the ways in which the evolution of
linguistic analysis launched by structuralism has benefited
those historians who took note of it.
Ferdinand
Saussure, credited as the pioneer of structuralism,
first suggested that “signifiers” (words) are not intrinsically
born from “the signified” (concepts), but are in fact
arbitrarily assigned by cultures. Clark explains: “as
unions of sound image (“signifiers”) and concepts (“the
signified”), signs acquire their meaning chiefly through
their difference from each other within a language system”
[45]. Significant for history, Saussure also stated
that when humans use language, they personalize it to
express themselves in the speech act. Clark believes
that this attention to the relationships between words
and concepts opened the door for further inquiry into
how other non-linguistic systems of signs (such as rituals,
gestures, and signals) could be explored.
This
denaturalization of linguistics was furthered by the
work of Levi-Strauss’s Structural Anthropology, which
was one of the first theoretical models to truly impact
the historical discipline, and remains something with
which historians grapple. Strauss interpreted all culture
as being linguistically structured. His main goal was
to teach anthropologists to understand phenomena by
seeing them as conflicts born from an underlying system
of relations, and to pinpoint these opposing forces.
Explicitly arguing against the Hegelian idea that history
is progress, and attempting to forge a discipline that
does more than simply understand why certain events
follow others, Strauss asserted that the humanism and
undue focus on the subject in history implies that historical
facts are not a given, but constituted by the historian.
History, according to Strauss, is never simply an account,
but instead a history for a purpose declared
(often implicitly) by the historian.
Clark
reminds her readers that however popular structuralism
became, its critiques were equally notable. Its critics,
such as Ricoeur, argued that structuralism left no way
for language to take hold of reality. Others such as
Derrida attacked Strauss’s tendency to ignore writing
in favor of speech; he believed that writing couldn’t
be subordinated to speech acts if signs are completely
unmotivated. Perry Anderson, on the other hand, focused
on the differences between actions and language; he
believed that cultural phenomena such as marriage and
kinship structures cannot be correlated with language.
To this, Strauss replied that he was not theorizing
about individual speech acts (parole), but
the system of speech (langue). Clark summarizes
these debates by stating that the lasting benefits of
structuralism for history lie in the denaturalization
of culture, the theme of discontinuity (because historians
often search for continuity and attribute meaning to
it), and the exercise of breaking down and rebuilding
the object of study in order to understand the relationships
by which it operates.
Shifting
back to the historical discipline, Chapter 4 is Clark’s
historiography of the annalists, in which she explains
the shift away from positivism and historians’ lingering
resistance to philosophical theory. In a continuing
attempt to liken history to science and write a ‘total
history’ annalists abandoned the literary narrative
and developed a new style based upon the meticulous
utilization of documents with the goal of pure, objective
knowledge. Rejecting event history as amateurish, they
concentrated less on descriptions of events, and more
upon statistics, quantifiable data, and the analysis
of problems. Early annalises did not shy away
from the fact that the present is the primary motivation
for the writing of history, and that historians’ analyses
are always organized by their own questions.
Important
for her later prescriptions, Clark also discusses the
Mentalité historians, who focused on
the intellectual mechanisms, sentiments, and behaviors
of humans. For Clark, the most important contribution
of the Mentalité school was from Lucien
Febvre, who sought to conceptualize the “mental tools”
available to any given society; that is, what could
or couldn’t be thought by individuals. This, according
to Clark, initiated a new type of intellectual history,
or a history of ideas. Rather than focusing only on
elites and “high” literary texts, Mentalité
historians studied the thoughts and ideas of non-intellectuals
in an attempt to conceptualize collective attitudes
and behavior.
This
concentration on common people was taken up by Macrohistorians,
who re-embraced literary narrative and argued against
historical determinism and the histories that emphasized
statistics and universality. Alternatively, Macrohistorians
sought to reconstruct the daily experiences of common
people. Clark cites Giovanni Levi, who claimed that
Macrohistory “possesses a superior ability to define
and measure public signs and symbols in their social
particularity, rather than to homogenize them,” and
thus provides a “thicker description” than Geertzian
anthropology [76]. However, through all the developments
Clark discusses in this chapter, she maintains that
Even
the most celebrated historians of the twentieth century
display little concern for the epistemological problems
attending the writing of history, and sometimes attack
those who even raise such issues from discussion.
Although analytical philosophy of history tried, and
failed, to contribute a satisfactory theoretical assessment
of history’s status, and structuralism seemed at best
lukewarm (and often hostile) to the claims of history,
historians themselves contributed even less to the
examination of epistemological issues attending historical
work [84-85].
In
Chapter 5, Clark elaborates further upon the discussion
on historians’ employment of narrative, further demonstrating
the debates between the two main schools of historians—those
who utilize a literary-oriented history-as-narrative,
and those who aim for an objective history-as-science.
Clark points out, “It is significant that in the Anglophone
world, it was analytical philosophers who encouraged
the discussion of narrative among historians, while
[…] in France, interest in narrative in relation to
historiography developed under […] that of literary
criticisms and discourse analysis.” [xx] Historians
in favor of narrative, such as W.B. Gallie, argued:
“historical explanation lies in the ability to follow
a narrative” [87]. Historians of this camp argue that
history should tell stories, and that the significance
of the past can be found only in the context of a story.
Philosopher Louis Mink argues that narrative is a “primary
and irreducible human capacity” [88]. But the critics
of narrative have been unsympathetic to these claims,
accusing narrative history of being amateurish, fictitious,
and existing without the capacity for falsifiability.
After a thorough summary of the strongest points of
contention within the debate, Clark concludes, “the
ways in which theorists called attention to the ideological
dimensions of literature are provocative for those who
work on premodern texts, the primary aims of which are
variously to persuade, exalt, denigrate, and denounce”
[105].
In
Chapter 6, Clark evaluates what she calls the “new intellectual
history,” credited to Arthur O. Lovejoy and R.G. Collingwood.
She argues that their work, despite the criticism it
endured, is particularly instructive to premodern historians.
Lovejoy, for his part, distanced the history of ideas
from the history of philosophy, arguing that intellectual
historians “dismantle systems of thought into ‘unit-ideas,’
which are then traced through various eras and disciplines.”
He suggested that historians, taking multiple disciplines
into account, evaluate the ways in which words and concepts
fall in and out of favor with writers of a particular
period, or even across eras. He asked historians to
consider how “new beliefs and intellectual fashions”
were established and employed, and how and why they
were eventually replaced by other beliefs.
Collingwood,
whom Clark claims was a forerunner in the intellectual
history that would develop in the late twentieth century,
argued that history should be organized by problems
and questions. Historian should evaluate the questions
that the author of any given text was trying to answer.
While attacking positivist history, Collingwood did
not shy away from the idea that historians are informed
by the present, and argued that they should frame a
problem to be solved, and then evaluate the sources
accordingly, rather than simply reporting on whatever
information they find. He argued that causation lies
in the mind of the agent, and that historians can attempt
to reconstruct this causation by understanding the relationship
between the motivation of a text’s author and the cultural
forces acting upon him. Clark calls for a more sympathetic
reevaluation of both of these historians’ heavily-criticized
theories.
In
Chapter 7 Clark further evaluates the relationship between
text and context for the historical discipline. Recent
theory has called into question the assumptions by traditional
historians, who argued that the primary role of the
historian lies in differentiating texts from contexts,
and texts from documents, rather than the task of forging
new theory concerning the nature of texts. She cites
scholars such as Geertz, the anthropologist who suggested
that cultural rituals and norms can be evaluated as
texts, and historian Hayden White, who discounted the
idea that texts and contexts were always separate entities.
She suggests that the notions of text as informed by
literary theory, contextualism, and political theory
can be helpful to historians.
Post-structuralists,
whom Clark points out were active even during the advent
of structuralism, were open to seeing texts as dialogues,
theorizing that there is no text that is not affected
by another text. They concentrated on the inherent contradictions
within and between texts in order to forge a more complex
notion of interpretation. Others, such as Barthes, focused
on the difference between a “work” and a “text.” He
claimed that the work is the material object, but the
“text” is held in language, and that readers create
and assign meaning, rather than consuming it. Clark
further addresses this topic of meaning as assigned
by the author and the reader. Post-structuralist theory
has called into question the authority of the author,
and the discernability of his intention. Foucault, for
instance, dismisses authorial intention, and inquires
instead about the modes of the existence of his discourse
and how it is circulated and appropriated by readers.
Contextualists
such as Quentin Skinner assess context as a method of
unlocking meaning in a text and expands the notion of
context from social and economic to also consider “linguistic,
generic, and ideological contexts” [138] to determine
meaning as it was assigned through language by the particular
society in which the text was produced. Rather than
dismissing the discernabilty of authorial intention
completely, he argues that while the meaning of a text
may not be discernable (due to the gap between authors
and readers), the intention of the author is unproblematic
to find.
J.G.A.
Pocock, the other contextualist that Clark cites, agrees
with Skinner that language is a context in itself, but
disagrees that authorial intention is always possible
to understand. He argues that this task is possible,
but quite complex. According to Skinner, scholars must
assess the actions and intentions that were both conscious
and unconscious to the author. He also stresses the
importance of the unsaid, and promotes the notion that
scholars must likewise assess the intentions and actions
that the author might have performed, as well as those
he could not have.
Critics
of contextualism, as cited by Clark, have noted that
the theories of both Skinner and Pocock have not accounted
for linguistic changes or unconventional uses of language.
Thus, they argue, questions of meaning are individual
rather than conventional or collective. Other critics
question the ways in which historians chose the contexts,
and whether the existence of a single context that unlocks
the entire meaning of a text. Derrida, whom Clark identifies
as the most influential critic of contextualism, argued
that the “arbitrariness of the sign” disrupts the certainty
of contexts in relation to text. Determining the context,
he argues, is never purely theoretical, and never unmotivated
or disinterested. Furthermore, he addresses the relationship
of speech and writing, arguing that the two cannot be
assimilated, because of the absolute distance between
author and reader, which is dissimilar to a speech-act.
Writing, according to Derrida, continues to act long
after the author is absent, which negates the importance
of authorial intent. Concluding this discussion, Clark
argues that contextualism is inadequate due to its appeal
to context (which is problematically discerned) as an
explanatory model. Championing instead the questions
raised by literary theorists, Clark argues that these
methods are more useful to premodern historians, because
of their ability to assess texts of the distant past
with a readership that spans centuries, rather than
attempting to assimilate such texts into a model of
speech acts, as advocated by contextualists and interpretive
anthropologists.
In
her final chapter, Clark specifically addresses the
concerns of premodern scholars, and how they might selectively
utilize the theories explicated in the preceding chapters.
Such historians, Clark asserts, accept that historical
questions are marked by issues of the present. They
understand, for the most part, that the grand narrative
often cloaks ideological intentions and provides a false
sense of continuity. Premodern historians also must
understand the problematic issues of authorial intention
and the proliferation of meaning across centuries and
cultures. The difficulty for classicists and premodern
historians, Clark argues, has been that they could not
easily adopt post-structuralist theory as it was advocated
by social historians. The texts of premodern historians
are dissimilar to the documents of data used by social
historians, and require literary interpretation.
Clark
praises the work of historian Gabrielle Spiegel, who
focused on “the social logic of the text,” which Clark
explicates as a double focus: first to conceptualize
the mode of production (not authorial intention) and
second, the “surplus of signification” that readers
have found and will find within it [163].
Clark
also argues that the texts of early Christianity are
ripe for the focus on the “political unconscious” rather
than just the affective, aesthetic, and ethical dimensions.
She also advocates the use of deconstruction to explore
the silences, gaps, and omissions underlying a text.
To conclude, Clark borrows the idea of Febvre’s “mental
tools” to advocate that historians use all of the mental
tools available to them, suggesting that they utilize
recent philosophical developments to contribute to the
formation of a new intellectual history.
The
bulk of History, Theory, Text is devoted to
the debates between historians and philosophers, thus,
for those unfamiliar with the historiography of these
debates, the density of the book requires careful reading
in order to tease out the implications for each field,
some of which Clark does not make explicit. Due to the
relatively short length of the book, considering the
depth and range of topics, it is an extremely condensed
work often requiring the re-reading of certain passages.
However, absorption of the material is made easier by
Clark’s skillful use of notes—only the most relevant
information is included in the text; all references
and commentary are included in the copious and carefully
organized endnotes. Because of this, readers who are
interested in further reading on a specific topic are
directed to the best sources, without having to search
through a large volume. Clark’s own arguments are balanced,
clear, and are always consistent with her thesis. However,
they are minimal, which leaves the reader desiring more
of her unmistakably expert opinions.
While
Clark suggestions of the application of linguistic theory
are aimed at her own field, premodern history, the book
can be useful to any historian looking to develop new
and innovative methodologies. Newer fields of history,
such as the histories of gender and sexuality, which
require new methods and theories in order to discover
fresh sources as well as understand traditional sources
in a new context, are ripe for the employment of philosophical
concepts. Hopefully, because such fields are often interdisciplinary
in nature, those scholars will be less resistant to
reading and using philosophy in their work than historians
have been in the past.
Overall,
History, Theory, Text is a valuable contribution to
both historians and philosophers alike—historians looking
to understand how history can benefit from the work
of philosophers, and philosophers who wish to understand
the ways in which their theories can be applied to other
disciplines. Likewise, as a fair and balanced lesson
in historiography, this book is an excellent source
for students learning the role of professional historians
and the ways in which the academic disciplines have
interacted in the last century.
|