Catherine
MacKinnon,
Women’s
Lives, Men’s Laws (Cambridge: Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press,
2005, $39.95, 558 pages, ISBN 0-674-01540-1)—Kristen
Chamberland, California State University, Long Beach
Catherine
MacKinnon has had a long career as a feminist lawyer,
theorist, teacher, and activist. Most noted for her
pioneering work in developing the legal definitions
of sexual harassment and pornography, MacKinnon is also
known for her brilliant, yet uncompromising stance on
issues of sexual inequality. In her latest book, Women’s
Lives, Men’s Laws, MacKinnon offers a collection
of previously uncollected essays, dating from 1980 through
the present. While the essays address a myriad of different
social and political topics, they are connected by a
common focus on the sexual inequality and inconsistency
inherent in U.S. law, and the conflicts this creates
in the lives of women.
Dividing
the book into two parts, MacKinnon first scrutinizes
equality as it currently exists in U.S. law, and offers
suggestions as to how it might be reframed, re-envisioned,
and rehabilitated to not only consider women, but to
give them the solid tools they need to improve their
experiences. In the second section of Part I, she employs
these ideas while focusing more specifically on sexual
abuse, under which she lumps everything from sexual
harassment to prostitution and sexual assault—all
of which, for MacKinnon, are similar sex-based crimes
committed against women. In Part II, MacKinnon delves
into the role of speech in the law and in society and
discusses how even much of the speech that aims to (or
claims to) liberate women actually reinforces their
inequality and subjugation. Not surprisingly, the second
section of this part focuses entirely on pornography,
one of MacKinnon’s favorite evils. But in the
first section, she likewise attacks psychotherapy, history,
liberalism, and the media, claiming that these institutions,
while seeking to liberate women, have only masked the
worst abuses and perpetuated male dominance.
Beginning
her book with a chapter about the failed Equal Rights
Amendment, from a book review written in 1987, MacKinnon
frames the equality debate, but she also sets out a
very aggressive stance that will track through the rest
of her essays, which were written over the next twenty
years. MacKinnon argues that not enough people have
considered the potential of the ERA in its earliest
conception. She believes that it might have been a “new
departure.” She suggests that we imagine an ERA
that not only condemns the types of inequalities that
men visit upon other men, but the inequalities specifically
affecting women. She asks that we talk of an ERA that
“criticize(s) the legal standards under Title
VII that essentially assume that the status quo is nondiscriminatory”
and removes the requirement that intention must be proved
in discrimination cases. Furthermore, she calls for
an ERA that recognizes “abuses of women that have
never been recognized,” such as pornography [20].
Berating the ERA for not forging enough change is MacKinnon’s
way of setting up the legal arguments that follow.
In
Chapter 4, MacKinnon exposes the deepest roots of inequality
in western law. Because current theories of “formal
equality” stemmed from Aristotle’s notions
of sameness and difference, equality is guaranteed only
to those who are “similarly situated,” meaning
“alike.” She points out that even the Fourteenth
Amendment is based upon the idea that “one must
be the same as a relevant competitor to be entitled
to equality of treatment” [45]. Thus, because
Aristotle also deemed men and women to be essentially
different, they can be systematically excluded from
laws guaranteeing equal treatment. She argues that if
equality is sameness and gender is difference, then
even the notion of sexual equality is an oxymoron. But
more importantly, she delves further into Aristotle’s
idea of gender difference. She references an example
he gives about sex difference—that men show courage
through commanding and women show it by obeying. Thus,
to Aristotle, not only are men and women different,
but there exists a hierarchy based upon power through
giving and obeying of orders. She argues that “once
the reality of gender is faced, it becomes clear the
extent to which the laws, the legal system, the state
as such, and relations between states have built in
the experiences of the dominant and have been built
from the perspective of those who created them”
[54]. It is not a conspiracy theory, according to MacKinnon,
but merely a “political system of institutionalized
interest supported by social facts of patterned behaviors
and its embodiment in legal doctrine and philosophy”
[54].
In
order to effectively correct this deep-seated inequality
in our legal system, MacKinnon reminds us that we must
address all inequality, especially that based explicitly
on sex difference. She advocates institutionalizing
social equality though legal initiatives. First, she
states, we must carefully articulate the absence of
equality in society, and then “put legal power
to redress it into the hands of affected groups through
law” [57]. She believes that a legal system that
can treat women like equals might also finally relinquish
lingering inequalities among men.
Since
the basis of legal inequality in the US lies in its
own Constitution, the articulation of sexual inequality
that MacKinnon advocates begins with questioning our
loyalties to this document. In Chapter 6, “Freedom
From Unreal Loyalties,” she asks why women should
be loyal to a constitution that, from its conception,
never considered their interests. She stresses that
she is not considering the moral value of the Constitution,
but its legitimacy. To the degree that the Constitution
is unequal, it is illegitimate, and MacKinnon argues
that it will only be legitimate once it lives up to
its own promises. Because only equality can make the
Constitution legitimate, “its treatment is central
to answering the question of why we should be loyal
to the Constitution” [69]. She argues that because
the constitution is not always faithfully interpreted,
further statutes and litigations are necessary, so that
the document might encompass all those who are supposed
to be loyal to it.
MacKinnon
concludes the first section of Part I with an essay
written in 2003, “The Power to Change,”
which further elaborates on the progress of women using
the legal system to “challenge the hierarchy of
men over women that has been built into law.”
While she is still claiming that “most women think
of law as alien, subject to influence that they do not
have, ignorant of the realities they live,” she
concedes that there has been some positive change. In
her notes, she even admits that a majority of law school
applicants in 2000 were women. Her theme here is exposure.
While her rhetoric tends to remain a little sensational,
(for instance, she claims that “in working with
law, women have learned that the system of male supremacy
is like a vampire: it thrives on women’s blood
but shrivels in the light of day” [106]), she
shows how women have worked within the system to combat
the inequalities they experience. By publicizing formerly
private crimes such as harassment, sexual abuse, torture,
and prostitution trafficking, women have exposed the
systematic and institutional nature of their inequality.
Section
B of the first part of Women’s Lives, Men’s
Laws deals exclusively with sexual abuse. The focus,
not surprisingly, remains on sexual harassment and prostitution,
the causes to which MacKinnon remains most devoted.
In Chapter 12, an article originally published in the
Yale Law Journal in 2001, she frames the debate
concerning the crime of sexual harassment as crime based
on sexual (in)equality. Though this chapter is somewhat
repetitive, it makes clear the legal debates over sexual
(in)equality. The difficulty with sexual (in)equality
law, she points out, lies in the ideals of sameness
and difference which she highlighted earlier in the
book. In order to receive equal treatment, women need
to prove a “sameness” with men; but in order
to prosecute crimes that are committed almost exclusively
against women (sexual harassment, for instance), they
must admit sexual difference.
This
pragmatic need to claim sexual difference in order to
determine that certain crimes are sex-based necessarily
creates problems for equity feminists and anti-essentialists.
It is understandable that anti-essentialists rail against
the existence of the notion of an essential, universal
Woman, especially because this notion of Woman has been
responsible for the worst inequalities in the treatment
of women, notably in law, education, and medicine. In
her notes, MacKinnon firmly disagrees with those scholars
who have labeled her an essentialist, and provides numerous
accounts of scholars who refute such claims. In her
writing, both in this book and in previous pieces, MacKinnon
consistently asserts the particularities in women’s
experiences, primarily based on race and class. However,
while she effectively argues against the notion of inherent
qualities that make one female, she never explicitly
denies that there are such things.
In
typical MacKinnon style, Chapter 10’s essay, “Prostitution
and Civil Rights” from a 1992 symposium talk,
methodically insists that prostitution is unquestionably
a violation of just about every civil right imaginable.
Exercising her passionate rhetorical skill, MacKinnon
writes that "in prostitution, women are tortured
through repeated rape [and] are prostituted precisely
in order to be degraded and subjected to cruel and brutal
treatment without human limits” [151]. She also
argues that prostitution is akin to rape because “in
rape, the security of women’s person is stolen;
it prostitution it is stolen and sold” [152].
From this, she presents arguments that prostitution
violates women’s right to security, personhood,
liberty, privacy, property ownership, speech, freedom
from involuntary arrest, equality, and even life. For
MacKinnon, pimps are always men; they are always in
complete control; and all prostitution is a form of
slavery begun my men as pimps and perpetuated by men
as tricks. There are no degrees of severity in the violence,
in the risks, or in the rewards. Obviously, this impassioned,
unyielding argument is highly effective if the reader
already agrees with the most basic premises.
For
this situation, MacKinnon advocates changes in the law
to support women in prostitution, beyond the simple
elimination of discriminatory criminal laws, such as
those who punish prostitutes but not their customers.
She suggests that the Thirteenth Amendment should be
applied to prostitution as well as other forms of slavery,
because it requires “a showing of legal or physical
force, used or threatened, to secure service which must
be ‘distinctly personal service in which one person
possesses virtually unlimited authority over another”
[156]. Arguing that prostitutes would leave the life
if they could, she claims that legal action should be
taken against those enforcing the involuntary servitude.
She advocates this action being developed through both
criminal and civil law.
Part
Two of Women’s Lives, Men’s Laws
begins with a collection of chapters concerning "institutions"
such as psychotherapy, liberalism, and history. In these
essays, MacKinnon analyzes the way in which words and
speech have affected the practice of inequality. It
is in these chapters, particularly those on psychotherapy
and history, that MacKinnon most ardently argues that
men’s sexuality dominates our institutions. For
instance, in her assay “Does Sexuality Have a
History” (Chapter 21), MacKinnon criticizes the
framework historians use for evaluating desire in historical
context, claiming that they can’t effectively
evaluate experience because they are operating from
an assumption that “sex is good and more sex is
better” and “sex is pleasure.” Thus,
writes MacKinnon, “it follows from the history
of sexuality as a history of pleasure that it cannot
be the history of oppression…” [270]. She
suggests that these assumptions ignore the realities
of abuse, and that in order to factor those realities
into the larger narrative, historians must write on
what evidence exists, and “forget about what is
not there” [271]. She is urging historians to
track such changes as rape statistics, reports of abuse,
and the explosion of the pornography industry not as
anomalies, but as the foundations of a male-dominated
system of sexuality that is not necessarily a positive
one.
The
last section of MacKinnon’s book contains the
brunt of her arguments against pornography. She argues
that the primary reason for the increase in pornography
has been that its “real harm—the violation
of women and children that is essential to its making
and inevitable through its use—has been legally
and socially obscured.” This harm could be overlooked
because, she argues,
The pornographers, who are pimps, take people who are already socially powerless—the poor, the young, the innocent, the used and used up, the desperate, the female—and deepen their invisibility and their silence. Through pornography, their subjection is made sexually enjoyable, sexually enjoyed, sex itself. Women and children who are made to perform for pornography are also made to act as if they are enjoying themselves [300].
Like
her stance on prostitution, MacKinnon’s condemnation
of pornography is unwavering and without exception.
According to MacKinnon (and her collaborator, the late
Andrea Dworkin), pornography harms all women, not just
the women who participate in its creation, because it
sexualizes women’s inequality and thus makes that
inequality sexy. Furthermore, she claims that
Every act that is exacted from the women in the pornography, who are typically made to act as they are enjoying themselves, is acted out on yet more women integral to the pornography’s consumption. Women and children on whom it is acted out are given no choice about seeing the pornography or performing the sex. They are held down while the pornography is held up […] [302]”
For
MacKinnon, only harm can come from pornography, both
its creation and consumption. It is not a healthy outlet
for desire or fantasy, but a tool for the sexual degradation
of every woman, by inciting as much violence as it depicts.
Sex cannot be separated from violence in pornography,
and there can be no porn without violence, because all
porn depicts the rape of a woman in bondage.
She
offers no conclusion in this collection of essays. Her
tale of pornography legislation ends in defeat. She
concludes her last essay by reporting that the pornography
industry continues to grow and be more and more pervasive.
She states that “the age of first pornography’s
consumption is probably dropping, and the age of the
average rapist is ever younger” [372], thereby
further pushing her link between the consumption of
porn and actions of violence by the consumers. All in
all, a bleak picture.
Overall,
it is a far-reaching book, with wide-ranging topics
and prescriptions. Her framing of legal issues is obviously
well-informed, practical, and logical. As always, her
arguments are tight and her writing is forceful, confident,
and imperturbable. She does not waver; she does not
back off of contentious issues. She claims victories
where they can be claimed and gives solutions to forge
the way ahead. So why are some readers left so cold?
The
answer is simple. Third-wave feminists simply don’t
accept a wholesale victimization theory. MacKinnon’s
charge that all women are victims oppressed by men is
an assumption that is not comfortably accepted by young
feminists, who tend to characterize themselves in many
ways that have nothing to do with gender. For MacKinnon,
the basis of difference is gender, further complicated
by class and race. But women are all disadvantaged and
subject to the same harms, according to MacKinnon, and
most young, educated feminists would argue that class
plays a larger role in equality than gender.
Also,
while most third-wave feminists don’t deny the
scale of sexual violence, abuse, and harassment committed
against women, they are less likely to characterize
all women as victims, and are more likely to take women’s
choices and considerations into action. For MacKinnon,
women have no choice and little agency, because of the
political equality they are subjected to, and the social
climate in which they live. But young feminists are
more willing to take responsibility for their choices,
and take advantage of what agency they have. They are
proud of this, and are resistant to the idea of being
lumped under old theories of across-the-board victimhood.
In the eyes of many a a third-waver, MacKinnon is out
of touch with recent ideas, developments, and advantages
for women.
For
instance, in Chapter 3, “Law in the Everyday Life
of Women,” when claiming that “most women
will tell you that law has little to do with their everyday
lives,” MacKinnon is referring to “most
women” for whom she characterizes life as a “constant
cycle of minutiae with few landmarks or dramatic demarcations
of time, a litany of needs met but never satisfied.”
Generalizations like this are risky in today’s
feminism. The “facts” that MacKinnon states
as if they are obvious are debatable for many women,
and certainly don’t apply across class and race
lines, much less over national boundaries. Instead of
being galvanizing, these blunt, bald statements tend
to be a distraction to a critical third-wave reader,
pulling attention away from her more reasonable arguments.
In this same chapter, MacKinnon argues that women feel
out of touch with the law because it doesn’t address
the “deepest, simplest, and most widespread atrocities
of women’s everyday lives” [34]. Of course,
she is referring to issues of sexual assault, sexual
relations, domestic violence. Yet her insistence that
women are totally powerless is unconvincing to many
third-wavers, who cannot identify with statements like,
“Women’s exclusion from law and marginality
within it does not make the law inactive in women’s
subordination day to day. The fact that women have nothing
to say about a sphere of life does not mean it does
not affect us.” MacKinnon’s characterization
of women seems foreign to an educated third-waver. By
saying that “women seldom have much to say in
these matters yet live their consequences every day
in factories, behind counters, in beds, on streets,
in their heads, and in the eyes and at the hands of
men, where the everyday lives of most women are largely
lived out” [35] MacKinnon is painting a picture
of women that seems archaic to many. Even if the life
she describes is still the reality for many women, it
certainly doesn’t apply to all, and by insisting
that it does, MacKinnon distances herself unnecessarily
from her audience.
Part
of this distance is due to MacKinnon’s considerable
attention to underprivileged classes and races, which
does ensure that her feminism is not exclusive to the
ideals of educated, economically advantaged white women
(something for which many early feminists received criticism).
However, while reminding white women that their experiences
aren’t universal, she seems to ignore many of
the achievements and positive advancements of these
women, proclaiming such bold statements as “People
dominate animals, men dominate women” [92]. Statements
like this seem contrary to the experiences of women
(such as MacKinnon herself) who are employed as attorneys,
lawmakers, lobbyists, and heads of corporations. By
not often acknowledging these important advancements,
MacKinnon leaves her readers with a sense that important
changes have been meaningless, and many women feel that
this is not the case.
If
she seems out of touch to the average third-wave feminist,
she seems completely archaic and unreasonable to a sex-positive
third-waver. Dismissing any ideas of positive sexual
subjectivity, MacKinnon only characterizes women as
objects, slaves, and targets in the face of pornography,
medicine, even their own marriages. Claiming that women
in pornography and even in relationships only fake their
enjoyment in order to survive, she completely disregards
the possibilities of women’s desire. Her refusal
to admit that there exists any non-violent, non-subjugating
pornography negates the opinions of women who find some
porn stimulating and erotic. Many sex-positive third-wavers
are able to play with notions of domination and submission,
without assuming that what is depicted in pornography
or fantasized about necessarily has a correlation with
real experience. Furthermore, most sex-positive third-wavers
question MacKinnon’s assumptions of women’s
victimhood and are able to find degrees of liberation
and agency in most aspects of the sex industry. Thus,
it is the very uncompromising spirit that gained MacKinnon
so much attention and respect in the 1980s that is beginning
to detract from her arguments today. Modern feminists
tend to demand the type of leniency, nuance, and further
interpretation that MacKinnon is simply not willing
to give.
Furthermore,
because MacKinnon’s analysis and prescriptions
are limited to legal theory and possible changes to
the law, one wonders if these will be effective against
the social forces that drive many of the issues she
describes. Antiporn legislation might change the industry,
but it does little to understand or conceptualize the
demand that causes its creation in the first place.
Sexual harassment laws give women the tools to fight
workplace behavior and practice, but they do little
to focus on the intent or assumptions behind it. In
Chapter 9, MacKinnon questions whether women really
have the ability to give legitimate consent to sexual
activity, based upon their negative social conditioning.
Here, she compares the consent of women to the implied
consent of animals, saying that we cannot know whether
either is meaningful. If this is true, it hints at a
deeply rooted problem, one that cannot be solved by
litigation, because it means that the current laws and
social mores were shaped by a mentality so severe that
it strips women of the ability to make choices, even
when they believe they are. Obviously, the scope of
her work could not encompass all aspects of inequality
or prescribe one perfect method for solving the problems
it creates. But one tends to wonder while reading this
book, whether MacKinnon is clearly aware of the depth
of the social unbalance to which she refers.
Despite
its limitations, this book is a considerable contribution
to the debates about feminism and legal theory. Its
wide range of topics and tight, concise analysis make
it a good read for scholars of feminism as well as of
legal theory. Yet its passionate rhetoric, frank discussion
of contentious issues, and extensive explanatory notes
makes it accessible to more than just the academic audience;
it’s a book for anyone who desires a crash course
in the discourse of women and the law. |