The Death Penalty: An American History
Stuart Banner
Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2002.
$29.95, 385 pages, ISBN 0674007514.
Philippe Chassaigne
Université de Tours
Stuart Banners book opens and closes with the narrative of an execution.
The first one, which took place in 1821, was that of 16-year old Stephen Clark,
found guilty of setting fire to a building at night a few weeks before, and accordingly
sentenced to be hanged, since arson was a capital crime in his home state of
Massachusetts, as in many other American states at the time. In spite of a vigorous
opinion campaign for having his sentence commuted to imprisonment, he was hanged
in front of a crowd numbering hundreds of people, which was of common occurrence
at the time (some even totalled many thousands and were, all in all, fashionable
social gatherings). Instead of putting on a brave face, as many convicted criminals
did, he nearly fainted and was unable to perform his last dying speech (the
moralising speech the condemned was expected to deliver before his execution,
warning people, especially younger ones, not to follow his example), which had
to be read by the minister who had attended him on his way from the prison. The
rope was then tied around his neck and he was launched into eternity as
the contemporaries used to say. The second narrative is that of A.J. Bannisters
execution, in 1997. He had been sentenced to death 15 years earlier for a murder
which might have been a contract killing; it is however difficult to be sure,
since his court-appointed lawyer performed a below-average job and was unable
to even check the validity of Bannisters defence (that the gun had discharged
accidentally during a fight). The following 15 years were spent going from one
appeal court to another, up to the US Supreme Court, to obtain Bannisters
reprieve. All in vain. In the meantime, Bannister had become something of a
media star: he had written an autobiographical book, given interviews to various
media,
and a host of human rights associations rallied in his favour. He was executed
by an injection of lethal chemicals in his arm in front of a small assembly
of witnesses, both state officials and relatives of his victim, while a handful
of demonstrators camped outside the state prison where the execution was performed.
His last words were that the state of Missouri was committing a premeditated
murder far graver than his own crime.
The confrontation between the two stories says it all, or almost: in two centuries,
the death penalty has been increasingly removed from public view; delays between
the pronouncing of the sentence and its implementation tend to grow longer
and longer, because of protracted litigation, appeals, etc. The actual method
of
taking a criminals life has been thought over and over again, in order
to make it as civilized and painless as possible, considering that
putting an end to his life was the penalty, not making him suffer on top of it
(him, or his, becausethis has not changedhistorically
men have always outnumbered women on Death Row). Instead of accepting their fate
as a just reward for their crime, and making it public, criminals sentenced to
death now challenge the right for the justice system to take their life
and
make it public.
Stuart Banners book is a clear and straightforward account of what happened
in the meantime. Very much like a textbook, but with carefully chosen, and highly
relevant incursions into cultural history. It is highly significant that the
bulk of the book (8 out of 10 chapters) deals with the pre-1950 period: Banners
aim is obviously to convey what capital punishment meant to the early Americans,
since, obviously, the pros and cons of capital punishment have hardly changed
ever since. In fact, the American History depicted here is less that
of the death penalty in the US than that of the debate about capital punishment
in the US. Right from the start, i.e. since the independence, there have been
opponents to the death penalty as a remnant from the Ancien Regime,
when the US were the Thirteen Colonies of a mother country whose penal code numbered
an apparently ever-increasing number of capital crimes. They, however, were originally
very few, since capital punishment was considered as the standard penalty for
most crimes, something that not only pertained to retribution, but also gave
the criminal a possibility for achieving last minute salvation. Hence the ceremonial
surrounding an execution, or the emphasis put on the last dying speech urging
the people attending the execution to mend their ways. Such was the strength
of conformity that most of the criminals executed wanted to deliver a speech
that would impress those (the hundreds or thousands) who were to hear it. Banner
offers here a wide range of evidence providing many insights into the minds
of the contemporaries, and their perception of the death penalty as a part
of the
things-that-be.
Opposition to the death penalty came in fact from a variety of angles: some
considered it as the remnant of a bygone age, incompatible with the US status
as an egalitarian
Republic devoted to progress and the pursuit of happiness; others were no doubt
influenced by the reforms undertaken in late-eighteenth- and early-nineteenth-century
Europe, where the death penalty, if rarely altogether abolished, was confined
to an increasingly restricted number of crimes (murder, treason
). Most
important, in Bannisters view, was the change in sensibility which made
large parts of the public increasingly sensitive to the spectacle of other peoples
sufferingbe they criminals convicted of particularly heinous crimes. In
fact, the abolitionist movement developed in pace with the anti-slavery movement
and the campaign against cruelty to animals. Hence, the end of the barbarous
treatments sometimes inflicted to the criminals dead bodies, such as
quartering, disembowelling, etc.
And what about the rise of utilitarianism? It is widely remembered that in the
view of Michel Foucault and his disciples (see his Discipline and Punish [1977],
or Michael Ignatieffs A Just Measure of Pain [1979]) the search
for a more efficient way of punishment, one that moreover would be compatible
with the principles of the new, capitalism-based society that was emerging
at the time, and not humanitarian feeling, was the driving force behind the
judiciary
reforms of the early nineteenth century; thus, instead of being put to death,
most criminals were given up to a reformed prison system and when possible
used as a cheap workforce by local industrialists. For the New Left inspired
school of revisionist historians, most prominent from the late
1960s to the 1980s, the judicial reforms of the early nineteenth century, with
a reduction
in the number of capital crimes and the rise of the prison as the standard
method of punishment, were a clever device from the rising middle classes to
impose
not less, but better punishment, and to enforce the new economic
system of capitalism on the working classes. Without denying the importance
of utilitarianism, Banner displays enough evidence to silence those who would
interpret
these reforms as first and foremost a rulers conjuration. One
is in fact struck by the importance given to moral considerations, by the recurrence
of words such as humanity, or progress, under the pen
of those who were fighting against capital punishment.
The pace, however, was uneven. First, the abolitionist movement did not gain
any substantial strength until the 1820s. It was stronger in the North than
in the South, for obvious reasons: in a society based on the peculiar institution,
the death penalty was considered as the ultimate guarantee of the social order
and, indeed, such verdicts were far more frequently passed against coloured
than non-coloured people. However, even in the North, the abolitionist movement
failed
to reach its ultimate objective. Banner offers a clear and extremely detailed
account of the arguments used by each side in the debate, and of the piecemeal
way state legislatures progressively, but not regularly, nor consistently,
abolished the death penalty for crimes other than murder and, sometimes, treason.
Executions continued while the debates were going on, yet in different ways.
A major change came in the second third of the nineteenth century, when executions
were progressively withdrawn from public view to be performed inside the jail
yard. This aimed at putting an end to what was then seen as morbid voyeurisman
interesting change in mentalities, when one thinks that until then, the spectacle
of an execution was supposed to improve the morality of those who attended it
and to put them back on the right path. Of course, this was a gradual process,
which, again, originated in the North (Connecticut, 1830) and slowly spread to
the South. A second major change was the search for betteri.e. less painfulways
of executing criminals than hanging. Banner finely documents the rising concern
about executions which were not cleanly performed, leading to terrible scenes
of criminals suffocating for long minutes before actually dying (while the working
principle of execution by hanging is to administer instant death by breaking
the criminals neck); another cause for concern was to make sure that the
condemned person was dead, since there were plenty of stories of criminals being
resuscitated and enjoying a peaceful life after their execution.
Since the nineteenth century was that of science, science did have its way:
the electric chair was invented at the end of the 1880s and came in use early
in
the following decade, first in New York, then in Ohio, Massachusetts, New Jersey,
etc. It rapidly gained popularity as a less painful and less repulsive to watch
way of administering death. Other devices were also resorted to: in the Mormon
state of Utah, criminals were shot by a firing squad; execution by gas was
adopted in Nevada in 1921, followed by 10 other states, all of them westerners
or southerners,
i.e. the parts of the US where hanging was still popular and where the electric
chair had failed to gain popularity (there is clearly here an interesting point
of cultural history that would deserve better treatment).
However, the debates were not over. There were still people advocating that
electrocution and gas were methods of punishment which were just as horrible
and inhumane as
hanging; in fact, the mere spectacle of scientists grappling to find a more
humane way of administering death offered a field day to opponents who argued
that the
thus indirectly avowed inhumanity of capital punishment was a sufficient cause
for abolishing it altogether. At the same time the decline in the number of
executions actually perpetrated did not seem to foster an increase in the crime
rate; and
more and more scientists began to question whether criminal behaviour was a
product of deliberate action or the result of personality traits developed
by the interaction
of the criminals heredity and his environment, thus removing the very basis
of capital punishment, that the criminal was responsible for what he had done;
so, an increasing number of state legislatures decided to abolish capital punishment.
Michigan had been the first as early as 1846, but only 4 states had done so by
1875; some did it only to restore it a few years later (e.g. Iowa, where the
death penalty was abolished in 1872 only to be reinstated in 1878). The pace
quickened in the early twentieth century, generally in states where no executions
had taken place for a long time: 8 legislatures (Kansas, Washington, Oregon,
Arizona
) decided against capital punishment between 1907 and 1917, and,
in a bunch of other states (Connecticut, Ohio, California
), abolitionists
came fairly close to victory. The peculiar setting of the interwar years, with
the rise of organised crime, the Red Scare, prohibition, Christian fundamentalism,
stopped this evolution for a while and many abolitionist states returned to
the death penalty, but it was more an option offered to the juries than a sentence
they actually resorted to, and the number of executions kept on declining consistently.
Seen in such a light, the Supreme Courts decision of 1972, ruling the death
penalty unconstitutional, as cruel and unusual punishment in violation
of the Eighth Amendment, and the reversal of its decision in 1976, will appear
less inconsistent this side of the Atlantic (as we often consider all things
American). The first date may have been the high tide of liberalism, and the
second may have heralded a switch to the conservatism that was to dominate American
politics from the 1980s on. Above all, it reproduced at the federal level the
fluctuating attitudes towards capital punishment that happened many times before
at a more local level. The arguments used by the Supreme Court were hardly innovative:
the fact that capital punishment was cruel and unusual was a staple
of the abolitionist discourse right from the early nineteenth century. The Court
also pointed out that the death penalty was distributed at random, varying from
one jury to another, something which again had been criticised by generations
of abolitionists. However, the death penalty had been ruled unconstitutional
on a technicality (jury discretion made it randomly administered), not on a substantive
argument. Consequently, as soon as the Courts decision was published, a
significant number of states had the death penalty re-enacted with the right
provisions to abide by the new rules. They also switched to a new method of execution,
through the injection of lethal chemicals (a method now used by the overwhelming
majority of the states with capital punishment), clearly the less cruel
and inhuman method of administering death. Opinion polls showed that
the population, regardless of colour, class, gender or region, was stronger
than
ever before in favour of the death penalty. In the 1990s, the number of
executions was more or less on a par with that of the 1950s (above the 90 mark),
and the number of inmates on Death Rowreached an all-time high with over
3,000 people. It must be stressed, however, that due to the rise in population
that had occurred in the meantime, the rate of execution was necessarily
lower. Moreover, it would be interesting to compare these figures, located
at the very end of the judicial process, with those of the people tried and
sentenced,
to get a broader picturewhich Banner fails to do. He succeeds better
when he tries to figure out why capital punishment is so much back in favour,
putting
the US on equal footing with such authoritarian states as China, Iran, or Saudi
Arabia, making them an exception among fellow Western states and exposing them
to international criticisms from organizations like Amnesty International.
The question of the death penalty deterring crime is today of less importance,
even
though this was its original purpose: the statistical evidence is unclear,
and varies from one criminologist to another. In fact, supporting capital punishment
has become first a way of reacting against the feeling of insecurity which,
up
to recently, was fuelled by rising crime statistics, but also something of
a moral statement, a way of saying that real dangerous criminals had to expiate
their deed instead of being rehabilitated. It happens however that a fraction
of those waiting on Death Row across the country are in fact innocent, the
victims
of judicial errors, as regularly found out by stubborn lawyers and investigative
journalists. Here now lies the haphazard bit (it now depends on the skills
of lawyers and/or the mobilisation of public opinion) that prompted the Supreme
Court to rule capital punishment unconstitutional in 1972; it may be today
the
most potent argument in favour of its abolition.